Socrates and Plato
I. The Good for Human Beings: The Problem
-
A. Introductory Remarks
-
B. The Character of Cephalos
-
C. The Nature of Philosophical Analysis
-
D. Polemarchus and Thrasymachus: Two Attempts
to Analyze Moral Uprightness
-
E. Glaucon and Adeimantus: A Digression on Moral
Uprightness and Happiness
II. Moral Uprightness (Diakosune)
-
A. The Analogy between the State and the Individual
-
B. The Education of the Guardians
-
C. The Three Parts of the Soul
-
D. The Cardinal Virtues
-
E. Why the Morally Virtuous are Better Off than the
Morally Corrupt
III. The Philosopher as the Paradigm of Human Flourishing
-
A. The Definition of the Philosopher
-
B. The Characteristics of the Philosopher
-
C. The Philosopher and Death
-
D. Why Philosophy is Unpopular in a Democracy
IV. The Theory of Forms
-
A. Knowledge of the Form of the Good
-
B. An Outline of the Theory of Forms
-
C. The Theory of Recollection
-
D. Critique of the Theory of Forms
V. Cosmology and Extrinsic Teleology
-
A. Cosmogony and Cosmology
-
B. Explanation and Extrinsic Teleology
IA. Introductory Remarks
-
On Philosophy: Synthetic Vision vs. Analytic Depth
-
On Socrates:
-
As portrayed by Plato
-
Focus on ethical questions
-
Socrates and the Sophists -- what, exactly, is the difference?
-
On Plato:
-
Three periods: early, middle, late ..... but some think that
the 28 dialogues were carefully planned out to be read in sequence as a
pedagogical introduction to the philosophical life and can thus be divided
into seven tetralogies
(this particular arrangement is due to Bernard Suzanne ).
-
The dialogue form
-
On the Republic
-
Plato and democracy
-
Our focus: moral rather than political
IB. The Character of Cephalos
-
Cephalos seems to be morally upright, and yet he is (relatively) unreflective.
This raises three questions:
-
Does Cephalos have moral knowledge?
-
Can philosophical reflection yield moral knowledge?
-
What sort of grasp of moral truths does philosophical reflection presuppose?
IC. The Nature of Philosophical Analysis
-
1. What is it that is analyzed when F-ness (e.g., moral uprightness, piety,
virtue, etc.) is analyzed? There are three possible answers to this question:
-
The meaning of the word <F>
-
The concept <F-ness>
-
An abstract reality signified by the term <F> and the concept
<F-ness>
-
2. To analyze F-ness is to give an account (logos), i.e., to produce
a formula, that
-
applies to all things that are F
-
applies only to things that are F
-
pinpoints what makes a thing F.
-
Concerning this last condition, compare the following two formulas from
the Meno:
-
shape = what always accompanies color
-
shape = the outermost boundary of a solid
ID. Polemarchus and Thrasymachus: Two Attempts
to Analyze Moral Uprightness
Polemarchus:
-
Moral Uprightness (diakosune) = The skill (techne) by which
one gives each his due
-
Counterexample: Insane Man
-
Moral Uprightness = The skill by which one gives benefits to friends
and injuries to enemies.
-
Worries: Is moral uprightness a skill? What if our friends are bad?
-
Moral Uprightness = The skill by which one gives benefits to good
people and injuries to bad people.
-
Worry: Does one who is morally righteous do harm to anyone?
Thrasymachus (compare with Callicles in the Gorgias):
-
Moral Uprightness = Doing that which is in the interest of the stronger
rather than that which is one's own interest. (Shades of Nietzsche.)
-
Question: Is it the righteous or the unrighteous who have the best
chance of being happy and flourishing human beings?
IE. Glaucon and Adeimantus: A Digression on
Moral Uprightness and Happiness
-
There are three sorts of goods:
-
Goods that are valued only for their consequences
-
Goods that are valued only for themselves
-
Goods that are valued both for their consequences and for themselves
-
Glaucon and Adeimantus: The common view is that moral uprightness
is good only because of its consequences and not because it is an intrinsic
excellence (arete).
Glaucon:
-
The origin and nature of moral uprightness = narrow self-interest.
For even though the best condition is clearly to be able to inflict injury
and yet avoid punishment in the pursuit of our narrow self-interest and
of the goods it requires, all of us have to settle for the best viable
condition, viz., to inflict no injury and to avoid punishment. In
that way we can get at least some of the goods we want without suffering
evil consequences. So we adopt conventions and laws that generally
reward "morally upright" conduct and punish "immoral" conduct, even though
we would each prefer to be able to act "immorally" with impunity in the
pursuit of our narrow and individual self-interest. (358e-359b)
-
We practice moral virtue only reluctantly. Witness the story of
the ring of Gyges (359d-360d)--after all, what would you do if you
had the ring? Wouldn't you act in a way analogous to that in which
Gyges acted?
-
It is not the case (as Socrates suggests) that any morally upright and
virtuous person is better off, or has a better life, than any morally corrupt
person. For we can easily imagine a morally corrupt man (A)
who has a reputation for being virtuous and thus reaps all the benefits
of being virtuous, and we can easily imagine a morally virtuous man (B)
who has a reputation for being corrupt and thus suffers all the consequences
of being wicked (360e-362c). Ask yourself: If you had to choose
between being A and being B, which would you choose?
Yet Socrates is committed to the claim that B, despite all his unjust
suffering, is better off (i.e., happier or closer to fulfilling the good
for human beings) than is A!!!.
Adeimantus:
-
Ordinary moral and religious education shows that we value moral virtuousness
not for itself but only for its consequences (reputation, honor, glory,
wealth, success, enjoyable afterlife, etc.) (362e-363e). ("Don't
lie, Peter, because if you do, people won't trust you and you won't be
a success in life." "Michael, keep on working hard and someday you
will be wealthy." "Don't sulk, Stephen, because if you act like that, you
will never be popular.")
-
Ordinary people all agree that moral goodness is a matter of convention
with no deep roots in our nature, and that being morally upright is much
more difficult, unpleasant, and burdensome than being morally corrupt.
In general, ordinary people are perfectly ready to admire and even to honor
wicked and morally corrupt individuals as long as those individuals are
rich or powerful or famous. Because of this, ordinary people generally
believe (even if they won't say so out loud) that anyone who has the chance
to be "immoral" with impunity is stupid and irrational if he isn't in fact
"immoral". What's more, even the gods can be bought off by expensive
rituals and sacrifices--so we need not even fear punishement in the afterlife
for being immoral (363e-367a).
-
Ask yourself: What would moral education be like if we really did value
moral uprightness for itself and not for its consequences?
IIA. The Analogy between the State and the
Individual
-
The nature of analogical reasoning
-
Analogical reasoning as a tool of discovery
-
Positive and negative analogy in the case at hand
IIB. The Education of the Guardians
-
The connection between sentiment and moral knowledge, and the importance
of shaping the passions or emotions through habituation (401e ff.).
(Contrast with Hume and Kant -- see C.S. Lewis's The Abolition of Man.)
-
The connection between self-love (or self-interest) and moral uprightness:
narrow self-love transformed into willing the good for others and for committing
oneself to a higher good that transcends one's own private good.
Self-love as the motive for the desire to become the sort of person who
is fit for genuine friendship and a commitment to make sacrifices for a
transcendent common good. (Plato as an alternative to Hobbes and
Kant.)
-
The importance of the moral community for conveying and promoting an appreciation
of a good that transcends narrow self-interest and that provides the moral
context and direction for all those crafts that have an intrinsic good
but are not of themselves directed toward the good for human beings.
-
The arts and the content of moral education -- gods, heroes, and good rhythms.
-
Pain, pleasure and strength of character -- courage, self-sufficiency,
seriousness, truthfulness, self-discipline, generosity, broadness of vision,
etc. No brutality or softness.
-
Constant Socratic theme: The parallel between health of the body
and health of the soul, i.e. between physical health and moral health.
IIC. The Three Parts of the Soul (psuche)
-
Reason (To logistikon) -------------------------------> The
guardians
-
The spirited element (ho thumos) ------------------> The
auxiliaries
-
Lower appetite (to epithumetikon) ------------------> The
commercial class
IID. The Cardinal Virtues
-
Prudence (practical wisdom): An excellence with respect to reason
-
Courage (fortitude): An excellence with respect to the spirited
element
-
Self-discipline (temperance): An excellence with respect to the
lower appetite
Moral Uprightness ("general justice"): A second-level excellence
by which one keeps the parts of the soul in a harmonious ordering, with
reason in control.
IIE. Why the Morally Virtuous are Better Off
than the Morally Corrupt
Moral uprightness: soul :: health: body
-
See the Hydra, the Lion, and the Man (588B-592B)
-
Question: Is it possible to know what is right and still do what
is wrong? (See Jordan's discussion of Aristotle's reply to Socrates
-- Jordan, 158-159)
IIIA. The Definition of the Philosopher
-
Philosopher = one whose heart is fixed on the true being (to
on) of things (480a).
-
Knowledge (episteme) -------------------> Being
-
Opinion (doxa) ------------------------> Becoming
-
Ignorance (agnoia) -----------------> Non-Being
-
The Philosopher as a moral authority (the philosopher-king) who knows what
health of the soul is and in whom non-philosophers can place their trust.
IIIB. The Characteristics of the Philosopher
(484a-487a)
-
Love of any branch of learning that reveals eternal realities
-
Truthfulness and singleminded devotion to the truth ("the inability to
consciously tolerate falsehood")
-
Self-discipline ("constitutionally incapable of taking seriously the things
which money can buy")
-
Magnanimity and breadth of vision ("a mind constantly striving for an overview
of the totality of things human and divine")
-
Courage
-
Moral Uprightness
-
Innate high intelligence
-
Excellent memory
-
Sense of proportion and elegance
(Compare Socrates in the Apology)
IIIC. The Philosopher and Death (Apology
and Phaedo)
-
Philosophy as a vocation (see Apology 38a)
-
The body as a hindrance to finding eternal realities (Phaedo, 64c-67b)
-
Asceticism and immortality: the philosophical life as a preparation for
death (see Phaedo, 83d-e)
-
Looking ahead: The Philosopher and (vs. ?) the Saint
IIID. Why Philosophy is Unpopular in a Democracy
-
True philosophy conflicts with skepticism and/or relativism about the
good for human beings
(The unruly crew: 488A-489A)
-
In democratic societies philosophy easily deteriorates into sophistry
(The wild animal trainer: 493A-493C)
IVA. Knowledge of the Form of the Good
-
The Simile of the Sun (506e-509c)
-
What should we want?
-
Philosophy as ascent and purification
-
The Divided Line and the Cave (509d-521b)
-
Knowledge (episteme) ----------------------------------->
Forms (Being)
-
Intellection (noesis)
-
Hypothetical Reasoning (dianoia)
-
Opinion (doxa) ---------------------------------------------> Sensible
Things (Becoming)
-
Belief (pistis)
-
Illusion (eikaisia)
IVB. An Outline of the Theory of Forms
-
The Big Claim:
We can have a deep understanding of the visible world only if we understand
it by reference to the world of eternal realities, which is "visible" only
to the soul.
-
The Properties of the Forms:
-
Eternal
-
Ungenerable
-
Imperishable
-
Unchanging
-
Non-sensible
-
Immaterial
-
Do not admit of their own opposites
(Shades of Parmenides)
-
The Forms and Particulars:
-
The Forms are exemplars which are approximated by sensible particulars
-
F-ness is perfectly F
-
x is F to degree n
-
A sensible particular is F because of its relation to F-ness
-
x participates in F-ness
-
x exemplifies F-ness
-
x has F-ness
(Question: What sort of causality is this, anyway?)
-
The Forms, Thought, and Language
-
The Forms are known through reason (noesis) by means of the giving
of an account (logos)
-
The Forms are what make sensible particulars intelligible to the
extent that they are. (Timaeus: The Forms impose order on an indeterminate
receptacle)
-
The Forms are signified in different ways by concrete and abstract terms:
-
<F-ness> signifies F-ness and is true of it
-
<F> signifies F-ness and is true of things that are F
IVC. The Theory of Recollection
-
The Paradox of the Learner (Meno)
-
Innate Ideas (See Phaedo on Equality: Shades of Descartes and Leibniz)
-
General Ideas: Where do they come from? (Abstraction vs. Illumination)
IVD. Critique of the Theory of Forms (See
the Parmenides)
-
Problems with mud and hair, but even more problems with unrestricted
generality (Russell's Paradox: see below)
-
Problems with Participation
-
The "Third Man" Argument
-
The Viability of Conceptualism
VA. Cosmogony and Cosmology
The universe is a perfect animal, spherical and rotating, fashioned
by God (the Demi-urge) in the Receptacle and patterned after the Forms,
which are images of God.
-
Receptacle----> Space (?)
-
Rotation----> Time
-
World Soul---> Fashioned from the Same, the Different, and Being
-
Body---> Fashioned from the Elements
-
Elements----> Isoceles and half equilateral triangles combining
to form regular solids:
-
Cube = earth
-
Tetrahedron = fire
-
Octahedron = air
-
Icosohedron = water
-
Individual Souls----> Created individually, making four kinds of
living things from the elements:
-
Stars (fire)
-
Birds (air)
-
Fish (water)
-
Mammals (earth)
VB. Explanation and Extrinsic Teleology
-
Four types of explanation (Phaedo)
-
Material
-
Efficient (moving)
-
Formal (the "safe explanation")
-
Final (teleological)
-
Some teleological notions
-
Tendency
-
Propensity
-
Intention
-
Purpose
-
End (Goal, Aim)
-
Good and evil (proper and defective relative to the end)
-
Extrinsic vs. Intrinsic Teleology
Russell's Paradox for Properties
-
Principle of generality: If 'is F' is a meaningful predicate,
then there is a Form F-ness.
(1) Some Forms (e.g., Moral uprightness, Redness) are such that they
do not exemplify themselves. (premise)
(2) So 'is a non-self-exemplifier' is a meaningful predicate
(premise)
(3) So there is a Form Being a non-self-exemplifier (call it
N). (From (1) and the principle of generality)
(4) N either does or does not exemplify itself. (Obvious)
(4a) If N does exemplify itself, then it does not exemplify
itself
(4b) If N does not exemplify itself, then it does exemplify itself
(5) So N exemplifies itself if and only if it does not
exemplify itself. (From 1, 2, and 3)
Therefore, N both does and does not exemplify itself--a contradiction.