The matter, however, is not so simple. There is a plethora of
texts in which St. Thomas speaks quite clearly of a ratio communis of the
analogous name. Indeed this seems to be involved in texts
where substance and accident are discussed as modes of being
differing from the transcendental modes.{1} Being is that
which our intellect first grasps and into which all other
conceptions are resolved. Resolution is the breaking up of
something into its parts, the reduction of the secondary to
the primary. Resolution to being, consequently implies that
all other concepts involve addition to that of being. What is
the manner of this addition? It cannot be the addition of a
nature extraneous to being, as difference is extraneous to
genus, since every nature is essentially being. Being is not a
genus and a concept can add to it only in the sense that it
expresses a mode of being that the term "being" itself does
not express. Thus far we would seem to be given to understand
that "being" expresses a common notion and that though
something may be addd to it the added note is not some
nature.{2} There are two ways in which words can express being
in a way "being" itself does not: first, such that a special
mode of being is expressed. This is the case with each of the
categories. Secondly, a term can express a mode of being which
belongs generally to being and is not confined to a given
category. This suggests a ratio
communis entis, say "that which has existence," a
notion which expresses a mode of being that the term "being"
itself does not express. Thus far we would seem to be given to
understand that "being" expresses a common notion and that
though something may be added to it the added note is not some
nature.{1} There are two ways in which words can express being
in a way "being" itself does not: first, such that a special
mode of being is expressed. This is the case with each of the
categories. Secondly, a term can express a mode of being which
belongs generally to being and is not confined to a given
category. This suggests a
ratio communis entis, say "that which has existence," a notion which
expresses no determinate mode of being, but is common to each
of the special, categorical modes. Moreover, the ratio substantiae will
express more than the ratio
communis entis, there will be at least an addition ratione and thus the
apparent equation of the notion of substance and that of being
said without qualification, an equation suggested by the texts
examined in the previous section, is called into question.
Prior to the notions of substance and accident, there is the
notion of being and insofar as "being" is taken to signify
this first and fundamental grasp of reality, it signifies a ratio communis.
Much the same point is made by St. Thomas
in his discussion of the transcendental name "good," although
this time he makes the point even more forcibly by citing a
threefold way in which something can be added to something
else.{3} They are: (1) the way in which accident adds to
substance, (2) the way in which addition leads to a
contraction and determination of the common, e.g. "man"
contracts and determines what "animal" signifies; (3) the way
in which something purely of reason is added to something.
Thus, when we say "blind man," we are not adding some real
nature, but a lack in the real order. However, though what is
added is in mind
alone, the addition of "blind" enables us to contract "man"
since not all men are blind. No such contraction is gotten by
adding "blind" to "tree" since no tree can see. Which of these
modes can be involved in an addition to ens universale? Not the
first since there is no natural thing which is "outside the
essence of universal being" though, of course, one thing can
be essentially different from another particular thing. With
certain qualification, the second made of addition is involved
in the distinction of the categories: unlike species with
reference to genus, this contraction and determination of
"universal being" is not had by the addition of any difference
which is outside the essence of being, but by expressing a
determinate mode of being (modus
essendi) which is founded in the very essence of the
thing. Such addition cannot explain such terms as "good,"
however, since good like being is divided equally into the ten
categories.
What is suggested, accordingly, is a ratio communis entis
other than and superior to the rationes of substance and accident.
Moreover, since they too escape confinement to one category,
the so-called transcendental notions will be shown to add
something of reason to the common notion of "being." From this
one might want to conclude that, while metaphysics may be
concerned first of all with substance when it turns to the
special modes of being, it can first occupy itself with the
notion of being which is prior to the categories and establish
the transcendental properties of being as being. Indeed, it
might even be maintained that this is proper level of
metaphysical considerations. Nor would it be surprising to be
told that concern with the ratio
communis entis is characteristically thomistic as
opposed to the Aristotelian penchant for substance, which is
only a special mode of being. Occupation with the ratio communis leads to
a deduction of the transcendental properties from esse, since there is
little else to work with in that common notion; this, more
than anything else, would recommend the acceptance of the ratio communis to
many contemporary thomists for it would seem to involve that
"putting of the accent" on esse
which is said to separate the metaphysics of St. Thomas from
all others, including that of Aristotle, which look to essence
as source of intelligibility in philosophical wisdom, thereby
putting a premium on "conceptual" thought.
In the previous section we cited the
procedure of the fifth book of the Metaphysics, in which Aristotle
distinguishes the various meanings of common names, as
indication that there is no common meaning of such names.
However, if we look somewhat more closely at this process of
distinguishing, we notice something : in discussing the
various meanings of "disposition," St. Thomas cites a ratio communis of the
name{4} At
the end of the analysis of the meanings of "principle," St.
Thomas writes, "And he reduces all the foregoing modes to
something common; he says that what is common in all the
mentioned modes is that that is said to be a principle which
is first either in the being of the thing, as the first part
of a thing is said to be a principle, or in the becoming of a
thing, as the first mover is said to be a principle and in
knowledge of the thing."{5} So too what is common to all modes
of "element" is to be first in something.{6} The discussion of
"one" is begun with this statement: "...those things which are
wholly indivisible are especially said to be one: because all
other modes are reduced to this one, since this is universally
true that whatever things have no division are because of this
said to be one."{7} So, in the discussion of "prior and
posterior": First he assigns the common notion of the prior
and posterior."{8} And there is a reduction of all modes of
"possible" to one{9} Indeed, when speaking of the subject of
metaphysics, St. Thomas speaks of "being" as prior to
substance. "The subject of this science, however, can be taken
either as it is commonly considered in the whole science, and
in this way it is being or one, or as to that which is its
principal concern, substance."{10}
Elsewhere as well, St Thomas speaks of the
ratio communis of the
analogous name. "Origin, however, can be considered in two
ways: either according to the common notion of origin, which
is for one thing to be from another, and thus one notion is
common to the origin, which is for one thing to be from
another, and thus one notion is common to the origin of
persons and the origin of creatures, not indeed by a community
of of univocation but of analogy: and similarly too the name
"principle".{11} Mortal and venial sin share a common notion,
albeit analogously.{12} "Person" can be taken to signify a
notion which abstracts from the things to which it is
analogously common.{13} So too the analogous cause of truth
communicates with its effect in name and a common notion.{14}
The term "passion," which is said in many ways, has a common
meaning.{15} Finally, with respect to the use of an analogous
term in an argument, we can cite a text mentioned in this
connection by Cajetan,{16} a text in which St. Thomas points
out that, although "generation" and "production" are not
univocally common to God the Son and creatures, a common
notion of these words is possible thanks to which the Son and
creatures communicate in the distribution of the term.{17}
We began by noticing that analogical
signification is said to be midway between univocation and
pure equivocation and that it participates something if these
extremes; indeed insofar as the analogous name is thought of
as more closely resembling pure equivocation, the accent will
be placed on the many rationes
signified and cautions expressed as to the use of an analogous
name in an argument since we may shift from one meaning to
another and end up with a four term syllogism. The texts we
looked at in the previous section stress the multiplicity of
the notions signified by the analogous name and seem not to
allow for a ratio communis.
The texts we have just examined, on the other hand, do speak
of a ratio communis
although, when they do, they are careful to distinguish it
from the common notion signified by the univocal name. If
there is a ratio communis
of the analogous name it is not equally common to its
inferiors. This is check enough, surely, against assuming that
wherever there is a common notion there is univocity.
Nevertheless, there remains at least a prima facie opposition
between these groups of texts and we must ask how they can be
reconciled. In pursuit of an answer to this query, we will
first recall the doctrine of analogical signification with
particular reference to the terminology St. Thomas uses to
describe it. Once this has been done, we shall examine the
contexts of many of the texts already quoted by investigating
the doctrine that being is not a genus. That investigation,
together with a detailed tracing of the extension of some
selected analogous names, should enable us to arrive at some
generalities with respect to St. Thomas' doctrine on the
nature of the ratio
communis of the analogous name.
{1} Cf. Q.D. de ver., q. 1, a. 1:
"Illud autem quod primo intellectus concipit quasi nocissimum, est
ens... Unde oportet quod omnes aliae conceptiones intellectus
accipiantur ex additione ad ens. Sed enti non potest addi aliquid
quasi extranea natura, per modum quo differentia additur generi,
vel accidens subiecto, quia quaelibet naura essentialiter est ens;
unde etiam probat Philosophus in III Metaphys. quod ens non potest
esse genus, sed secundum hoc aliqua dicuntur addere supra ens, in
quantum exprimunt ipsius modum, qui nomine ipsius entis non
exprimitur. Quod dupliciter contingit: uno modo ut modus expressus
sit aliquis specialis modus entis. Sunt enim diversi gradus
entitatis, secundum quosaccipiun tur diversi modi essendi, et
iuxta hos modos accipiuntur diversa rerum genera. Substantia enim
non addit supra ens aliquam differentiam, quae significet aliquam
differentiam super dditam enti, sed nomine substantiae exprimitur
quidam specialis modus essendi, scilicet per se ens; et ita est in
aliis generibus. Alio modo ita quod modus expressus sit modus
generaliter consequens omne ens..."
{2} Q.D.
de ver., q. 10, a. 11, ad 10: "...ens quod est primum per
communitatem, cum sit idem per essentiam rei cuilibet, nullus
proportionem excedit; et ideo in cognitione cuiuslibet rei ipsum
cognoscitur."
{3} Q.D. de ver., q. 21,
a. 1: "Dicendum quod tripliciter potest aliquid super alterum
addere. Uno modo quod addat aliquam rem quae sit extra essentiam
illius rei cui dicitur addi; sicut album addit super corpus, quia
essentia albedinis est praeter essentiam corporis. Alio modo
dicitur aliquid addi super alterum per modum contrahendi et
determinandi; sicut homo addit aliquid super animal: non quidem
ita quod sit in homine alia res quae sit penitus extra essentiam
animalis, alias oporteret dicere, quod non totum quod est homo
esset animal, set animal esset pars hominis; sed animal per
hominem contrahitur, quia id quod determinate et actualiter
continetur in ratione hominis, implicite et quasi potentialiter
continetur in ratione animalis... Tertio modo dicitur aliquid addere super alterum
secundum rationem tantum; quando scilicet aliquid est de ratione
unius quod non est de ratione alterius: quod tamen nihil est in
rerum natura, sed in ratione tantum, sive per illud contrahitur id
cui dicitur addi, sive non. Acecum enim addit aliquid supra
hominem, scilicet caecitatem, quae non est aliquid ens in natura,
sed rationis tantum, secundum quod ens est comprehendens
privationes; et per hoc homo contrahitur, non enim omnis homo
caecus est: sed cum dicimus talpam caecam, non fit per hoc additum
aliqua contractio."
{4} In V
Metaphysic., lect. 20, n. 1058: "...et ponit rationem communem
huius nominis Dispositio, dicens, quod dispositio nihil est alius
quam ordo partium in habente partes."
{5} Ibid., lect. 1, n. 761: "Recudit omnes praedictos modos ad
aliquid commune; et dicit quod commune in omnibus dictis modis
est, ut dicatur principium illud, quod est primum, aut in esse
rei, sicut prima pars rei dicitur principium, aut in fieri rei,
sicut primum movens dicitur principium, aut in rei cognitione."
{6} Ibid., lect. 4, n.
807.
{7} Ibid., lect. 8, n.
866: "...illa quae sunt penitus indivisibilia, maxime dicuntur
unum: quia ad hunc modum omnes alii modi reducuntur, quia
universaliter hoc est verum, quod quaecumque non habent
divisionem, secundum hoc dicuntur unum, inquantum divisionem non
habent."
{8} Ibid., lect. 13, n.
936: "Primo assignaat rationem communem prioris et posterioris."
{9} Ibid., lect 14, n.
975: "Reducit omnes modos possibilis et impossibilis ad unum
primum."
{10} "Subiectum autem huius scientiae potest accipi, vel sicut
communiter in tota scientia considerandum, cuius modi est ens et
unum: vel sicut id de quo est principalis intentio, ut
substantia." - Ibid.,
lect. 7, n. 842.
{11} "Potest autem origo considerari
dupliciter: aut secundum communem rationem originis, quae est
aliquid ab aliquo esse, et sic una ratio est communis ad originem
personarum et originem creaturarum, non quidem communitate
univocationis, sed analogiae: et similiter etiam nomen principii."
- I Sent., d. 29, q. 1,
a. 2, sol. 1.
{12} Q.D. de malo, q. 7,
a. 1, ad 1: "...duplex est divisio: una qua dividitur genus
univocum in suas species, quae ex aequo participant genus, sicut
animal in boyem et equum; alia est divisio communis analogi in ea
de quibus dicitur secundum prius et posterius; sicut ens dividitur
per substantiam et accidens, et per potentiam et actum; et in
talibus ratio communis perfecte
salvatur in uno; in aliis autem secundum quid et per
posterius; et tale est divisio peccati per veniale et mortale." -
Cf. ibid., ad 2:
"...veniale est differentia diminuens de ratione peccati; et talis
differentia invenitur in omnibus quae participant aliquod commune
imperfecte et secundum quid." Cf. ibid., ad. 7. - II Sent., d. 42, q. 1, a. 3: "...alia vero
divisio est eius quod est commune per analogiam, quod quidem
secundum perfectam rationem praedicatur de uno dividentium, et de
altero imperfecte et secundum quid, sicut ens dividitur in
substantiam et accidens, et in ens actu et in ens portentia: et
haec divisio est quasi media inter aequivocum et univocum; et
talis divisio est peccati in mortale et veniale: quia ratio
peccati perfecte in mortali invenitur; in veniali vero non nisi
imperfecte et secundum quid." Cf. ibid., ad 1. - IaIIae, q. 88, a. 1, ad 1: "...dicendum quod
divisio peccati venialis et mortalis non est divisio generis in
species, quae aequaliter participant rationem generis: set analogi
in ea de quibus praedicatur secundum prius et posterius. Et ideo
perfecta ratio peccati...convenit peccato morali. Peccatum autem
veniale dicitur peccatum secundum rationem imperfectam, et in
ordine ad peccatum mortale; sicut accidens dicitur ens in ordine
ad substantiam, secundum imperfectam rationem entis."
{13} "...dicendum quod ratio personae importat distinctionem in
communi; unde abstrahitur a quolibet modo distinctionis: et ideo
potest esse una ratio analogice in his quae diversimode
distinguuntur." - I Sent.,
d. 25, q. 1, a. 2, ad 5.
{14} In II Metaphysic.,
lect. 2, n. 294: "Nomen autem veritatis non est proprium slicui
speciei, sed se habet communiter ad omnia entia. Unde, quia illud
quod est causa veritatis, est causa communicans cum effectu in
nomine et ratione communi, sequitur quod illud, quod est
posterioribus causa ut sint vera, sit verissimum."
{15} IaIIae, q. 22, a.
1: "...pati dicitur tripliciter. Uno modo, communiter, secundum
quod omne recipere est pati, etiam si nihil abiiciatur a re...";
cf. Q.D. de ver., q. 26,
q. 1, a.2; III Sent., d.
15, q. 2, a. 1, sol. 2; infra
IV, 2.
{16} Op. cit., n. 107.
{17} Q.D.
de pot., q. 2, a. 5, ad 6: "...dicendum quod generatio
Filii et productio creaturarum non sunt unius rationis secundum
univocatione, sed secundum analogiam tantum. Dicit enim Basilius
quod accipere Filius habet communi cum omni creatura; et ratione
huius dicitur 'primogenitus omnis creaturae' et hac ratione
postest eius generatio productionibus creature communicari sub una
distributione."
© 2011 by the Estate of Ralph McInerny. All rights reserved including the right to translate or reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form.