Aristotle
I. Substance and Accident: The Categories
A. Introductory
Remarks
B. The division of being into
substance and Accident
C. Two Kinds of Predication
D. Theses about Primary and
Secondary Substance
E. Lingering Questions
II. The Analysis of Change
A. Preliminary
Remarks on Physics I
B. The Principles of Change:
Matter, Form, Privation
C. Unqualified Change
D. A Problem or Two
III. Nature, the Four Causes, and Intrinsic
Teleology
A. The Concept of
Nature
B. Nature as Matter and as Form
C. The Four Causes
D. Teleology vs. Blind
Spontaneity
E. Teleology in Plato and
Aristole
IV. The Soul
A. The Soul: Form
of a Living Substance
B. Kinds of Souls
C. Sensation and Intellection
D. Philosophical
Anthropology: the
Immateriality,
Immortality, Unicity of the Rational Soul
IA.
Introductory Remarks
- Aristotle as student of and critic of Plato
(amicus
Platonis, sed magis amicus veritatis)
- The division of logic and the philosophical sciences (see
below)
- Interpreting the Categories:
Things or terms?
IB. The Division of
Being into Substance and
Accident (preliminary framework for an account of how
unqualified change is possible)
The TRANSCENDENTALS (so-called
because they transcend
the
categories and are coextensive with being):
Every
being, regardless of
which category
it falls into, has the following transcendental
terms truly
predicable
of it:
being (ens) one (individual
or undivided) (unum) something real (res) entity (entitas) true (verum) good
(bonum) (see St. Thomas, Quaestiones disputatae de veritate,
q. 1, a.
1)
The CATEGORIES: Beyond this, being, which is
said in many
ways, is divided into the categories:
- Substance (answers to the question, "What
is it?"): that
which
is not present in a subject but exists per se,
i.e., in its own right, and not in
alio, i.e., not in something else.
That which is ousia, being or the really real in
the
paradigmatic
sense. This is the "privileged" sense of 'being' and its
focal
sense
--
all beings in the other categories are defined by their
relation
to substance. Each of the paradigmatic single members of the
category of substance is a primary substance that belongs to a natural
kind, a "this-such".
- primary substance:
singular substance,
e.g.
Plato, Socrates, Arnie
Aardvark, Ollie Oaktree, etc. (Corresponding linguistic
terms: proper
names
of primary substances.) That which neither is said of a
subject nor
is present in a subject. (Note: These
examples presuppose
but do not prove that the really real can come into
and pass
out
of existence. Aristotle's argument for this comes later, in the Physics.)
- secondary substance:
the nature or natural
kind or essence
or "what it is to be a
"
of a primary substance, e.g., human being, tree, tunnel
spider,
gold,
water, etc. (Corresponding linguistic terms: natural
kind
terms, including
both genera and species of those genera, right down to the
"lowest-level
species.") That which is said of a subject but is
not present
in a subject. (The reason for saying that secondary
substance
is not "in
a substance" will become clear below when we talk about
essential
predication.) Secondary substance can also be characterized
as
(a)
that which makes the primary substance to be a unified member of a
given kind
(the what
it is to be of that sort of thing); (b) that which is the
object
of
scientific knowledge (episteme); (c) that from which
a
thing's inseparable
accidents or properties flow;
and (d) the object of
the
so-called real definition of a thing (a definition
given in
terms
of genus and difference -- see below).
Primary substances can be divided taxonomically into
kinds
(secondary
substances = genera and species)
by adding differences
to genera at a higher level. Here is a very general taxonomy that
divides
substances by differences and goes from the most general genus (substance)
to the "lowest-level species" human being. In each
case the
second
member is further divided in the next level down, and all of the terms
in parentheses are included in the category of substance as secondary
substances:
- immaterial substance (= angel
or intelligence)
vs. material
substance
(= corporeal substance or body)
- inanimate material
substance (= element/mineral)
vs. animate
material substance (= living substance)
- non-sentient animate
material substance (= plant)
vs. sentient
animate material substance (= animal)
- non-rational sentient
animate material
substance (= non-rational animal)
vs. rational sentient animate material substance (=
human
being)
Hence, the category of substance gives us a taxonomy
from
which
theoretical inquiry can take its start. And the purpose of
such
inquiry
is to discover -- by reasoning from effects back to causes -- the
essences
and properties of primary substances.
- Accident
(answers to the
various
forms of the
question "How is it?"): that which is present in a
subject and
thus
exists in alio, but is not said of any subject.
This
is
the non-primary sense of 'being'. Each category of accidents
provides
the answers to various (further) questions that we can ask about a
substance.
Aristotle says that accidents are not "said of" a subject because he
apparently
has in mind that which is designated by an abstract term, e.g.,
Socrates's
wisdom -- which is a singular instance of wisdom and that by which
Socrates is wise. The concrete term
'wise',
on the other hand, is said of a subject and designates or signifies
singular
instances
(tropes) of wisdom. Here are the categories of accidents:
- quality: sensible
characteristics of the substance
(e.g., colors
and
sounds), shape,
active and passive powers, dispositions, habits
- quantity: dimensions of the
substance (continuous
quantity,
e.g., lines, surfaces:
the subject-matter of geometry); number (discrete quantity:
the subject-matter of arithmetic)
- relation: how the substance
stands with respect to
other
substances (e.g., mother of,
teacher of, to the left of, bigger than, etc.)
- where: place
- when: temporal characteristics
- action (acting): what the
substance is doing
- passion (being acted upon):
what is being done
to the substance
- having on: what the substance has
on (e.g.,
clothes, makeup)
- position (or posture):
how the substance's
parts are
ordered with respect
to one another
IC. Two Kinds of
Predication
- Accidental Predication:
Analyzable as a
(trans-categorial) relation
between two singular entities, one of which (accident)
has being
only insofar as it is
present
in or inheres in or is
(present) in the other (paradigmatically, a substance).
So an accidental predication presupposes that the substance in question
is already constituted as a member of some natural kind.
- 'Socrates is wise' is equivalent to 'A (singular
instance
of) wisdom
inheres
in Socrates' (--- and not 'participates in' or
'exemplifies'
the
Form Wisdom).
- Essential Predication:
Predication in which a
species,
genus, or
difference (i.e., some 'secondary substance linguistic term') is
predicated of a substance.
- 'Socrates is a human being' is not
equivalent to
'Human nature
inheres
in Socrates' ........
After all, how could his human nature, which constitutes
Socrates
as a human being, presuppose Socrates's existence in the way an
accident
presupposes and depends upon the substance it inheres in?
(Alternative positions, mistaken in Aristotle's view:
(a)
bare-particular theory and (b) bundle-theory).
Unanalyzability thesis:
When a substance term
(i.e., a species- or
genus-term) is predicated of a primary substance, the resulting
predication cannot
be analyzed as a relation between two singular entities.
ID. Theses about
Primary and Secondary
Substance
(from Categories, chap. 5)
- Primary Substance (PS):
- Every PS is a this-such, a
kinded individual, an
undivided
unity.
(There are no "bare particulars" or "bare substances"---sorry,
Anaximander)
- Every PS is an ultimate subject
of predication
and of
accidents,
but is not itself present in any subject, i.e., it does not itself inhere in any subject.
- If no PS existed, then no
accident would exist.
(Note the
contrast
with Plato's "qualitative" Forms.)
- No PS of a given species K
is more or
less a substance
of K
than any other PS of K.
- Every PS is such that it admits
of contrary
accidents while
remaining
numerically the same PS (vs. at least one
standard form of bundle-theory).
- Secondary Substance (SS):
- An SS is said of
a PS but is not present
in
a PS. (It's not present in
it because an SS
constitutes
a PS
as a
substance.)
- An SS exists only if it is
truly predicable of
some PS.
(Note
the contrast with Plato's "substantival" Forms, which exist whether or
not they are exemplified.)
- Among the SS's, the species is
more truly
substance than the
genus.
(It's 'closer' to the primary substance of which it is said.)
- An SS provides a privileged
answer to the
question "What is it?"
IE. Lingering
Questions
- How is unqualified
change possible, as it must be if plants
and
animals,
which come into and pass out of existence, are primary substances and
hence
really real? (Physics 1)
- How can plants and animals be primary substances
and hence
undivided unities,
given that they consist of elements and minerals? (Physics
2)
IIA.
Preliminary Remarks on Physics I
- Method of natural philosophy:
- From what is better known to
us to what
is
better known in
itself
- From what is complex to
principles and
causes
- From effects to
causes
- Basic Assumption:
- "Natural things are all or some of them subject to
change" (Sorry,
Zeno.)
- The principles of change:
- How many are there?
- What are they?
IIB. The Principles
of Change: Matter, Form,
Privation
Three
descriptions of a
single
ordinary qualified change, where a qualified change is a change with
respect
to accidents (Physics 1.7):
The third description is the most informative, since it makes clear
the main elements, viz., (i) the contraries
which serve as
the
formal terminus a quo or starting point
(ignorant-of-music)
and the formal terminus ad quem or endpoint
(knowing-music)
of
the change, and (ii) the substance which serves as
the
substratum
of the change. This, by the way, is Aristotle's reply to Parmenides'
argument against the possibility of change. What
is comes to
be in one sense from what is (the substratum with its
potentiality
for
the new accident) and in one sense from what is not (the
formal
terminus ad quem). Let's look at it more carefully:
- The ignorant-of-music man
becomes the knowing-music man.
- At the first level of
generality we have three
principles:
- ignorant-of-music = the privation
from
which the change proceeds.
- knowing-music = the accident
toward
which
the change proceeds
and which terminates the change.
- man = the substance
which perdures
through
the change and
is the subject first of the privation (with a potentiality for the
accident)
and then of the accident.
- At a higher level of generality
we can see that any
change
(even an unqualified change, if such is possible) would have to involve
three principles if it were a genuine change and not a mere succession
of wholly distinct entities:
- ignorant-of-music = the privation:
the
absence of the perfection
which will terminate the change.
- knowing-music = the form:
the
perfection
(including, but not necessarily limited, to accidents) that terminates
the change.
- man = the matter:
that which serves
(i) (before the change) as
the subject of
the privation and is in potentiality with respect to the form, and (ii)
(after the change) as the subject of the form. In other
words,
the matter is that
which
changes or is transformed.
- Notice that all three of these principles are
essential.
If the matter
already has the form, then it cannot attain it through a change. If the
matter acquires no form, then there is no change. If there is no matter
or common subject of both the form and the privation, then at best we
have
a succession in which one matter has the privation and
another--numerically
distinct--matter has the perfection. But this would not be a change,
strictly
speaking, since there would be no common subject, even if the two
distinct
matters existed continuously, one after the other, in the same place.
(A
more interesting case would put pressure on the notion of
continuity:
Suppose God were to annihilate the substance-cum-privation at t
and re-create the very same substance, now with the form, at t+e,
where e is a small as you please.)
- In general, then, the matter is
the principle of potentiality
or determinability,
that which persists through the change and is the
subject
first of the privation and then of the form; the form
is the
principle
of actuality
or determination,
that which
constitutes the actualization of the matter's
potentiality
for a given perfection.
- In qualified change, the matter
of the
change is a primary
substance and the form is an accident.
(Refer back
to
the list of accidents.)
There are three
basic types of qualified change, which all other types of qualified
change can be reduced to or traced back to (see On Generation and Corruption
1.4):
- alteration: change with
respect to quality
- augmentation/diminution:
change with respect
to quantity
- local motion: change with
respect to where
(place)
IIC. Unqualified
Change (Generation and Corruption)
Here we see the crux of Aristotle's anti-reductionistic
reply
to Parmenides,
Empedocles, Anaxagoras and the atomists--the explanation of how real
really
things (ousiai) can come into existence and pass out
of
existence.
What he has been working toward is a set of abstract concepts (a
technical
vocabulary, if you will) that helps us make sense of all
kinds
of
change, both qualified and unqualified. His method in setting up this
technical
vocabulary is to extend his account of qualified change by
analogy
to the case of unqualified change.
(Note: terminus
a quo = starting point and terminus ad quem =
ending point.) There are two relevant features:
- In qualified change something complex
or composite
is the total terminus a quo
(substance + formal
terminus
a quo, i.e. the privation), and something complex
or composite
is the total terminus ad quem
(substance + formal
terminus ad quem, i.e., the accidental form). More
graphically,
QUALIFIED
CHANGE
|
|
|
Total
terminus a quo =
|
matter
(the substance) +
|
formal
terminus a quo
(the privation)
|
Total
terminus ad quem=
|
matter
(the substance) +
|
formal
terminus ad quem
(the accidental
form)
|
- In qualified change what
is comes to be both
from what
is (the substance, which has the accidental form potentially)
and
from what
is not (the privation of a form had only potentially by the
substance).
Now let's look at a putative unqualified
change--e.g., the
coming-to-be
of a pig from a pig-sperm and pig-ovum:
The sperm and ovum become a pig (note: Aristotle
didn't have the biology exactly right, but that is irrelevant for the
big claim he is making):
- The pig-sperm and pig-ovum (terminus a quo)
must be thought
of as a complex
or composite,
viz., as a subject or substratum (matter) that
lacks
the form by which something is a pig and has a contrary form instead --
yet with the potentiality of taking on the form by which something is a
pig).
- The pig (terminus ad quem)
must likewise be thought
of as a complex
or composite, viz., as a subject or substratum that
has the
form
by which something is a pig.
- The matter of the change is thus something
capable of
"taking on" both
the form by which something is a mere pig-sperm or pig-ovum
and the form by
which
something is a pig. But notice that these forms are not accidental
forms, since they are constitutive of primary
substances and,
unlike
accidental forms, do not presuppose the existence of the relevant
substance.
Rather, each is a form by which something is a substance of a given
type -- in
other words, each is a substantial
form that makes a substance to
be
a substance of a particular natural kind and is the source of the unity
and activities that characterize substances of that natural
kind as
such (in this case, a living substance,
a pig) -- and not just as
collections of elements or of minerals, etc. Likewise, the
matter
of
such
a change is not itself a substance but is instead something capable of
becoming a substance -- even a living substance -- with
its own
distinctive
character and principles of organization -- in other words, it is primary
(or first)
matter that is in potentiality to a substantial form. (We
must here
make a distinction between proximate matter and remote
matter.
This will become clearer below.)
In sum, unqualified change is intelligible because terrestrial material
substances
are composite beings which have a principle (primary matter)
capable
of taking on and losing the principle (substantial form)
which
constitutes
a thing as a primary substance of a given kind. More graphically,
UNQUALIFIED
CHANGE
|
|
|
Total terminus
a quo =
|
matter
(primary matter) +
|
formal terminus
a quo
(the privation)
|
Total terminus
ad quem=
|
matter
(primary matter) +
|
formal terminus
ad quem
(the substantial
form)
|
In general, form is the principle of
determination, actuality
and perfection, whereas, in contrast, matter
is the
principle
of determinability, potentiality,
and perfectibility.
Indeed, we can see the form/matter distinction itself as an instance of
the more general distinction between act
(actuality) and potency
(potentiality), so that:
actuality : potentiality ::
substantial form : primary matter ::
accidental form : substance
A couple of
notes:
- First of all, the changes in nature are ordered, so
that
not just any
substance
can be immediately generated from any other substance.
Rather, a
substantial change is characteristically preceded by a series of
accidental
changes which prepare the way for the substantial change by rendering
the
substance which is the terminus a quo properly
disposed for a
substantial
change.
- Second, Aristotle designates "first" or "primary"
matter as
the matter
of a substantial change in order to emphasize the fact that the
substantial
form of a material or corporeal substance subordinates all
the
elements
and/or minerals to the new substance in such a way that the new
substance
is a genuine unity (or genuine mixture of lower-level substances),
with its own irreducible powers and characteristic activities, rather
than a mere aggregation of independent elemental substances. In
other
words, the elements entering into the constitution of a higher-level
substance no longer exist as
substances but have been "taken
up" into the new substance and into the structures and processes which
are
peculiar to
that new substance.
In general, at whatever level of description we specify the
material constituents of the new substance, those constituents, while
contributing active and passive powers to the new substances, are not
themselves substances. The substantial form dominates from the
top all the way down, and from the bottom all the way up.
This is most evident in the case of living things, but it is nearly as
evident in the case of minerals composed of elements. The
elements
and minerals taken up into a living substance remain not in their
substance
but in their active and passive powers. (More on this in a
moment.)
Hence, even though primary matter never exists as such without any
form,
the unity of generated substances demands that the immediate subject of
a substantial form be a matter capable of being totally "dominated by"
the principle that makes a generated substance to be of a certain
natural
kind. This is primary matter.
IID. A Problem or
Two
- The unity of substance (see Metaphysics,
books
7-9)
- Categories: Every primary
substance is a
this-such,
an undivided
unity.
- Physics: Every (terrestrial)
material primary
substance is "composed
of" primary matter and substantial form.
- Reductionism vs. emergentism (see Physics,
book
2)
Are there good reasons for thinking that plants and animals are primary
substances rather than just aggregates of primary substances (e.g., the
elements or atoms or "seeds"), as Empedocles and the Atomists and
Anaxagoras
held?
IIIA.
The Concept of Nature
(Physics 2)
- What is a nature?
- "An intrinsic source of change and staying
unchanged,
whether in
respect
of place, or growth and decay, or alteration."
- "A source and cause of change and remaining
unchanged in
that to which
it belongs primarily and per se."
- What is nature as a whole?
A dynamic system of interacting substances endowed by their natures
with active and passive causal powers and tendencies (vs. Plato's
world-soul,
which animates things from without).
- What has a nature?
- Answer A: Whatever exists by
nature rather than
by
art.
- Answer B: Anything that is a
K, where <K>
satisfies the following
formula: Every K, as a K, has a nature
- Answer C: Every naturally
occurring primary substance
THE BIG CLAIM (ANTI-REDUCTIONISM):
Minerals, plants,
and animals, as
such, have
natures ....
That is, they have intrinsic principles of change that are peculiar to
them as such and that go beyond the natures of their constituents taken
by themselves or as mere aggregates. And this is just what it
is
to be a primary substance that belongs to a natural kind. This entails that
"bottom-up"
scientific analysis and study of non-elemental substances will
invariably be
incomplete (though not without value); instead, such study needs to be
supplemented by "top-down" synthetic considerations.
Aristotle's view is
evoked in the following quote from Nobel Prize winner Robert
Laughlin's A Different
Universe: Reinventing Physics from the Bottom Down (2006):
"Over
the intervening years, as I have lived inside theoretical physics and
become familiar with its ways and historical currents, I have come to
understand the von Klitzing discovery as a watershed event, a defining
moment in which physical science stepped firmly out of the age of
reductionism into the age of emergence. This shift is usually
described in the popular press as the transition from the age of
physics into the age of biology, but that is not quite right.
What we are seeing is a transformation of world view in which the
objective of understanding nature by breaking it down into ever smaller
parts is supplanted by the objective of understanding how nature
organizes itself."
IIIB. Nature as
Matter and as Form
- Nature as matter: A substance's
lower-level
constituents
(elements,
minerals, etc.--at any level of description lower than the proper
species
of the relevant substance -- plug in whatever contemporary science
identifies as constituents).
- Nature as form:
- The specifying powers and tendencies of the proper
species as such
- Directedness toward an ideal paradigm of the
species
- As noted above, one reason why substantial form
is said
to inform primary
matter directly is that all the primary constituents are subordinated
to
the substantial form and cease to exist as substances in their own
right.
They exist, as it were, only in their powers, which are subordinated to
the new higher-level substance as a unified whole.
IIIC. The Four
Causes
- Intrinsic causes and principles of
explanation as
applied to natural substances:
- Material
cause (or matter) -- (a) the stuff of which a
substance is
made, at whatever
level of description (materia
in qua)
or (b) that which is acted upon to effect a change (materia ex qua)
[Note: these two notions pull apart in the case of
a thing created directly ex
nihilo -- it has a materia
in qua but no materia
ex qua]
- Formal
cause (or (substantial) form) -- the principle by which matter (materia in qua) is
constituted as a primary
substance belonging to a certain lowest-level natural kind.
(Can also apply to accidents, but right now we're concerned
with substantial form.)
- Extrinsic causes and principles of
explanation:
- Efficient cause (or agent) -- that which produces
something
by means of its acting
- Final
cause (teleological cause) -- that for the
sake of
which an effect
is produced by an agent
Some examples that help us get clear about the
difference
between efficient
and final causality:
- thermostat (mechanism vs. goal of the
operation of
the mechanism)
- homeostasis (alternate mechanisms for getting to
the same
goal)
- normal vs. abnormal development of a living
organism
(both involve
efficient
causes, but only the former achieves the built-in aim dictated by
thing's
nature or substantial form)
- human action (roughly, how I
did what I did vs. why
I
did
what I did)
Aristotle: "Sometimes the formal, efficient and final causes are one."
How can this be? Think of the normal growth and development of living
organisms.
That growth and development are (a) effected intrinsically by parts of
the substance itself [efficient cause], (b) ordered
toward an end
(roughly, flourishing
or the good for this sort of thing) [final
cause],
where (c)
this
end is determined by the natural kind to which the substance belongs
[formal
cause, as in substantial form]. We will now explore
the
ordered
nature
of such change in a bit more detail.
IIID. Teleology
vs. Blind Spontaneity
Preliminary distinctions:
- Deterministic efficient cause
vs. indeterministic
efficient
cause. This is not what we're talking
about here.
- End-oriented efficient cause
vs. blind
efficient cause [or,
perhaps better, blind sequence of states of a system, since Aristotle
denies
that any efficient cause operates wholly blindly -- even though some
particular effects
might be unaimed at or unintended by their agent causes].
This is
what we're talking about here.
Two scenarios:
Scenario 1--the normal development of a red oak
tree over
time along a number of relevant parameters of the red oak "system":
- AFFFF
.................................F......................>
- BBGGG................................G.......................>
- CCCHH................................H......................>
(a long and wonderful life for a red oak)
- DDDDI.................................I.......................>
- EEEEE..................................J.......................>
Scenario 2--the premature death of a red oak (* =
consequences of the
dreaded
red oak
blight on one or another relevant parameter of the red oak "system"):
AFFF*F* ...............................F*
BBGGG*.................................G*
CCCHH*................................H* (where
the
combination of F*, G*, H*, I*, J* = DEATH)
DDDDI*.................................I* EEEEE.....................................J*
The view of Aristotle's opponents:
- Nature, both as a whole and in the red-oak, is wholly
indifferent as
regards
these two scenarios. Efficient causes (if we can even talk of them on
this
view) or "mechanisms" work without any "directedness" in both cases, at
least without any directedness at the level of living things.
So
the red oak in Scenario 1 is not inherently a better or more perfect
red
oak than the one in Scenario 2. There are just atoms or
elements
(or whatever) churning away and "producing" effects in utter stupidity
and blindness in both cases. (Or if, like Hume, you're really
pessimistic about the ability of reason to penetrate the secrets of the
natural world, you won't talk about 'production' but simply about the
sequences of events (at whatever level) and profess ignorance
about why events occur in the sequence they do occur in.)
- Complete explanations of the two scenarios can in
principle
be given in
terms of efficient causes (or, better, blind mechanisms) alone, without
recourse to teleological notions like tendency, impediment,
prevention, compensation,
etc. Perhaps these complete explanations are too complicated
(for
now or even in principle) for human knowers to give, and so we
sometimes
have recourse to teleological notions to simplify things for
ourselves.
But these teleological notions have no ontological
significance.
That is, they don't correspond to anything distinctive in the real
world.
The elemental powers do not act for the sake of the
whole
organism, and a complete explanation of their action can thus be had
without referring to the role they play when directed by the organism as a whole.
- The "deviant" or "abnormal" is explicable wholly
by
recourse to mechanisms
and without recourse to the "normal" defined by some mysterious goals
supposedly
built into living bodies. To think otherwise is just dark-age
superstition.
Indeed, evaluative terms such as "deviant" or "abnormal" merely express
our own preferences or interests rather than any fact about nature.
Aristotle's rejoinder:
- Nature, both as a whole, and in the red oak, is not
indifferent
as regards the two scenarios. The red oak tree in Scenario 1 is a more
perfect instance of red-oak-ness than the one in Scenario 2.
The
natures of living things have built into them a tendency toward a norm-of-flourishing for their species.
- In order to understand the two scenarios completely
(i.e.,
scientifically)
we must attribute various goal-directed tendencies and propensities to
natures and to invoke notions like impediment, prevention,
compensation,
etc. The actions of elemental powers cannot be fully
understood
except by reference to the ends they serve within the whole
unified organism. Once we understand a given nature
scientifically, it is only
deviant cases that require special explanation.
- What happens "always or for the most part" is
indicative
(though not infallibly
so) of natural tendencies and propensities. What happens in nature
happens
because of the natural tendencies of the relevant agents. To
think
otherwise is to be the victim of new-age scientistic superstition.
Tendencies and Tomato Plants
- "Laws of Nature"
What exactly are we saying when we say "It is a law of
nature that
salt dissolves in water"? Not that every instance of salt is
dissolved
in water, or even that every instance of salt would dissolve if placed
in water. What, then? How about: Salt by
its nature
has
a (defeasible or impedible) tendency to dissolve in salt. The
aim
of science is thus to discover the natures of substances and hence
their
tendencies and characteristic ways of acting and being acted upon.
- Intrinsic Standards of Good and Evil
- 'This is a good tomato plant and that is a bad one'
- 'This is a good human being and that is a bad one'
Here we have the dreaded specter of Emotivism and
the (alleged) Fact/Value
Dichotomy vs.
Aristotle's view of nature, wherein
teleological
standards
of perfection or flourishing are built right into substances
(especially
living substances) by their very natures. These standards are in turn
the measure of the individual's progress toward or regress from the
norm for the species and for what is either in accord with a thing's nature or contrary to a thing's nature.
IIIE. Teleology in
Plato and Aristotle
- Plato: The ultimate source of
directedness in the
physical world
is extrinsic to to the physical world. (Shades of
Divine
Providence)
- Aristotle: The ultimate source
of directedness in
the physical world
is intrinsic to the physical world.
Question: Are these two positions,
appearances to the
contrary,
compatible with one another? Stay tuned.
IVA. The
Soul: Form of a Living Substance
- Distinction between two senses of
actuality:
- First actuality (or First
Act) = The possession
of
a power or set of powers
- Second actuality (or Second
Act) = The exercise
of
a power or set of powers
- Three (more or less) equivalent accounts
of the soul:
- Soul = The substance qua form
(i.e.,
the
substantial form) of a
natural body that has life potentially. ('Body' here is
apparently being used here for something non-organic, i.e., some
collection of elements as described in physics or inorganic chemistry.
Or else the soul is being included in the bodily organism.)
- Soul = The first actuality of a natural body that
has
life potentially. (Same remark about 'body'.)
- Soul = The first actuality of a natural body that
is
organized into organs -- i.e., is an organism. (Here 'body'
is
being used for an organism.)
- Salient points (neither dualism nor
materialism):
- The soul is the (substantial) form
of a
living
thing.
A living body is not a bodily organism without its form (= soul).
- Each soul has its own proper proximate matter.
- Of all the souls of living things, only the rational
soul is arguably subsistent (i.e., substance-like) and hence immaterial
and/or separable.
- Differences with Plato (and Descartes):
- The soul is an intrinsic,
rather than extrinsic,
mover
of
the body.
- The soul is ontologically constitutive
of,
rather than posterior
to, the bodily organism. That is, the soul is not
something
that is "added to" what is already a bodily substance.
Rather, the soul is the form or configuration of the matter
in
virtue of which this bodily substance is a tree, pig, aardvark, etc.
- Further difference with Descartes:
Plants
and animals are ensouled and are not reducible to machines, i.e., not
reducible to entities all of whose properties can be fully described in
terms of the fundamental forces of physics or of any science below
macro-biology.
IVB. Kinds of Souls
- Nutritive (Vegetative):
- Functions:
Nutrition, Reproduction
- Functions had by:
Plants, Brute Animals, Human
Beings
- Sentient:
- Functions: Sentient Cognition
(sensation,
memory,
imagination),
Sentient Appetite (desire, pleasure, pain, fear, audacity, etc.),
Locomotion
- Functions had by: Brute
Animals, Human Beings
- Rational:
- Functions: Intellective
Cognition (intellect:
concepts, propositions,
chains of reasoning), Intellective Appetite (will:
intention, consent,
choice, joy, etc.). (Aristotle has the notion of "rational
desire," though not a well-developed psychology of will.)
- Functions had by:
Human Beings
IVC. Sensation and
Intellection:
What follows is a
philosophical framework
into which more specialized scientific information can fit, the main
principle of which is that cognition must involve the union of the
knower and the known, i.e., of the cognitive power and the object of
cognition. In general, the human organism has a general
inclination toward intellective cognition of its environs, and this
begins with sentient cognition of a sort characteristic of higher
animals in general.
- Sensation (sentient cognition):
- Sensation involves the alteration of the sense
organs by
the objects
sensed.
- The objects sensed are external to the senses and
act upon
them to configure them in characteristic ways..
- The sensing faculty becomes like the object
sensed
(sensible species or
likeness), and this underlies the alteration (or configuration) of the
sense organ
counting
also as intentional and as having an interior side, i.e., as being a type of cognition, an act of sensing, as
well
as a physical state of the organ. Think
of the sensible
species or likeness of the object O
as
a certain configuration of the sense organ by virtue of which the animal senses-in-the-O-way through that organ.
- Sensing just is an operation of a physical or
material
organ, and this
is why each sense is limited to a fixed range and intensity of object.
In addition, sensings are the foundation for imaginings,
rememberings, etc.
- A
corresponding account can be given of feelings (or emotions).
Feelings are the interior aspect of certain physiological changes
wrought by sensings (or imaginings or rememberings, etc.), and they
have the objects of those sensings (or imaginings or rememberings, etc.) as their own
objects.
- Intellection (intellective cognition):
- Intellection is similar to sensation in that the
intellect becomes like
the object which is understood. Aristotle conceives of sensation and
intellection by
analogy with the composition of material substances from form
and
matter:
- Reality: Object constituted
by matter
configured by
form.
- Sensation: Matter* (sense
organ) is configured by
form* (sensible
likeness corresponding to object)
- Intellection: Matter**
(intellect as passive or
receptive) is
configured by form**
(intelligible likeness corresponding to object)
- Intellection, unlike sensation, is not limited to
present
singular
(as opposed to general) objects.
In fact, the unlimited nature of intellectual cognition is a sign that
even though the higher cognitive operations of the rational soul
presuppose
the operation of the material powers of sensation, memory, and
imagination,
these higher cognitive operations are not in themselves the operations
of material or bodily powers. As Aristotle envisions it, the
process of concept formation involves the intellect as an agent
configuring itself as a patient by illuminating the deliverances of the
sensory organs. Hence, the state of the various sensory
operations, and of the bodily organs that carry them out, profoundly
affects intellective cognition and affection. See General Note
below.
- Acts of the intellect:
abstraction of forms (product: concepts);
composition and
division (product: propositions); discursive reasoning
(product: knowledge)
- The intelligible likeness (or species) is that
by
which the object
is understood in a direct act, not that which is
understood (as
in representationalism, according to which the direct or immediate
objects
of sensation and intellection are mental objects or "ideas," to use the
term used by Locke and Descartes).
- General
note:
Despite what you might have heard in science classes or other
philosophy classes, Aristotelians are neither stupid nor Cartesians.
They understand
that brain injuries or diseases result in impaired cognitive
functioning in human beings. In fact, they explicitly assert
that
(in this life, at least) all cognitive functioning depends on various
bodily processes, especially those involving sentience (external
senses, imagination, sense-memory, comparative judgments with respect
to individuals, etc.). So
you do
not refute Aristotelianism by discovering (if you ever do) that certain
areas of the
brain support speech, higher cognition, religious belief, etc.
To
think otherwise is an ignoratio
elenchi, i.e., failure to understand your opponent's
position.
It's despicable, but widespread among certain cognitive scientists
and
their sympathizers. (Fanatical philosophy majors who are
really "into it" might want to check out "Good
News,
Your Soul Hasn't Died Quite Yet".)
IVD. Philosophical
Anthropology:
Immateriality,
Immortality, and Unicity of Rational Soul
- Immateriality: Intellective cognition,
unlike sentient cognition, is
not
the operation
of any bodily organ, even though it presupposes the operations of
bodily
organs in sensation, memory, and imagination.
- Immortality: Not clear what
Aristotle thought.
- Unicity: Averroes takes On
the Soul 3.5 to
imply that there
is just one intellect in both its active and passive functions. Some
(Augustine
at one time?) hold that there is just one active intellect, viz., an
active
intelligence (neo-Platonists) or God (Christians of a Platonist bent).
OVERVIEW OF ARISTOTLE'S WORKS: THE
DIVISION OF THE
SCIENCES
I. LOGIC (a necessary tool for the
philosophical
sciences):
- Categories: theory of terms
[abstracting].
- On Interpretation: theory of
propositions
[composing
and dividing].
- Prior Analytics: theory of
syllogistic [discursive
reasoning].
- Posterior Analytics: theory of
demonstrative
argument
[science].
- Topics: theory of dialectical
(non-demonstrative)
argument [opinion].
- Sophistical Refutations:
treatment of logical
fallacy.
II. PHILOSOPHICAL SCIENCES
- Theoretical (or Speculative) Philosophy:
has truth
as
its end, things
that have principles of movement and change within themselves as its
object,
and analysis into causes or principles as its method.
- Natural Philosophy: has as its
object things
that
(i) exist in matter,
(ii) have matter in their definition, and (iii) are subject to one or
more
types of change, i.e., local motion (change in place), alteration
(change
in quality), augmentation (change in quantity), or generation and
corruption
(substantial or unqualified change).
- Physics: general principles
of change and
motion,
causality, space
and time, proof of the first mover.
- On the Heavens: principles
of local motion.
- Meteorology: transmutation
of the elements
(chemistry).
- On Generation and Corruption:
principles of
alteration as ordered
to substantial change
- On the Soul: general
principles pertaining to
things subject to
augmentation (i.e., living things) (biology).
- On Sense and the Sensible Object
- On Memory and Reminiscence
- On Sleep
- On Dreams
- On the Parts of Animals
- On the Motion of Animals
- On the Generation of Animals
- Mathematics: has as its object
things that (i)
exist
in matter but
(ii) do not have matter in their definition and (iii) are not
changeable.
- First Philosophy: has as its
object things that
(i) do not exist
in matter and (ii) do not have matter in their definition and (iii) are
not changeable.
- Practical Philosophy: has
rightly ordered action as its end,
reason
and appetite
and their products as its object, and proceeding from causes to effects
as its method.
- Nichomachean Ethics: virtue in
the individual.
- Eudemian Ethics: virtue in the
individual.
- Politics: virtue in the
community.
- Rhetoric: theory of persuasive
arguments.
- Poetics: theory of art.
|
|