Intentionalism and internalism about phenomenal character

Jeff Speaks

March 12, 2006

1 Three plausible theses about perception
2 From minimal intentionalism to biconditional intentionalism
3 From externalism to ‘strong externalism’
4 Conclusions

1 Three plausible theses about perception

So far, I have suggested that we should adopt minimal intentionalism:

For any two experiences (of the same sense modality), if those two experiences have the same content, they also have the same phenomenal character.

I have also suggested that it is plausible to think that objects and natural kinds can be among the things represented in our experience. If this is right, then it looks as though the contents of one’s experience are not always fixed by one’s intrinsic properties. For consider two experiences which are identical in every respect but that they are directed at two distinct identical twins. If objects can be among the contents of experience, then it looks like these two experiences will have different contents. But the subjects of the two perceptions might have been in the same intrinsic state -- they might have been molecule-for-molecule duplicates. This sort of case strongly supports externalism about perceptual content:

Two experiences can differ in content without any corresponding change in the intrinsic properties of the perceiver.

(I.e., content does not supervene on intrinsic properties.)

But it is plausible to think that phenomenal character is not like content in this respect; i.e., it is plausible to think that phenomenal character does supervene on intrinsic properties of perceivers. As Hawthorne puts it,

“It is perfectly obvious that a region that does not contain a conscious being could not be a perfect duplicate of a region wholly containing me. It is just not intelligible to suppose that there be a perfect duplicate of a region wholly containing me which, owing to a difference in the laws of nature [or any other extrinsic fact], does not contain a conscious being.”

It may be overstating things to call this perfectly obvious. But there is an intuition here which seems to be difficult to reject. Let’s call the view here internalism about phenomenal character:

It is impossible for two experiences to differ in phenomenal character without any corresponding change in the intrinsic properties of the perceiver.

These three theses are not themselves contradictory. But many have thought that they were in tension. The tension can be expressed informally like this: intentionalism says that there is a necessary connection between content and phenomenal character; but if there’s this close of a link between them, how can one of these supervene on intrinsic properties, and the other not?

What we want to see is whether this tension can be turned into an argument against the conjunction of minimal intentionalism, externalism about content, and internalism about phenomenal character. The form this will take is the examination of various theses which have seemed plausible to many which can be added to this conjunction to make an inconsistent set of propositions.

2 From minimal intentionalism to biconditional intentionalism

Minimal intentionalism is a one direction supervenience claim: it says that sameness of content guarantees sameness of phenomenal character. Many people who endorse minimal intentionalism also go on to endorse the converse of this claim. This amounts to what I earlier called biconditional intentionalism:

Two experiences have the same content iff they have the same phenomenal character.

Let’s suppose that we adopt biconditional intentionalism. This can be shown to be inconsistent with the conjunction of internalism about phenomenal character and externalism about content as follows:

 

1.

A and B are in the same intrinsic state I and yet have experiences with different contents. (Externalism about content)

2.

Two experiences have the same content iff they have the same phenomenal character. (Biconditional intentionalism)

3.

The experiences of A and B have different phenomenal characters. (1,2)

4.

If two agents are in the same intrinsic state, then their experiences have the same phenomenal character. (Internalism about phenomenal character)

5.

The experiences of A and B have the same phenomenal character (1,4)



C.

The experiences of A and B have the same phenomenal character and have different phenomenal characters.

(Here ‘phenomenal character’ means something like ‘total phenomenal character.’)

So at least one of (1), (2), and (4) must be false.

We could block this argument by giving up biconditional intentionalism. But many people seem to think that minimal intentionalism without biconditional intentionalism is a kind of bizarre stopping point. Isn’t the whole motivation of intentionalism the reduction of phenomenal character to content? And doesn’t this involve saying that having an experience with a certain phenomenal character just is having an experience with a certain content? And doesn’t this kind of property identity entail biconditional intentionalism?

The property identity does entail this biconditional. But it’s not obvious that the reduction of phenomenal character to content should be the motivation for minimal intentionalism, for a few reasons:

So, to me, it seems plausible that the best way around this argument is be sticking with minimal intentionalism, but rejecting biconditional intentionalism.

3 From externalism to ‘strong externalism’

Above I suggested that there are good grounds for being an externalist about the contents of experiences. The formulation of this claim above is equivalent to the following:

There is some content of experience p such that a subject A could be having an experience with content p even though A’s molecule-for-molecule duplicate, A*, is not having an experience with content p.

The truth of this can only be explained by the fact that sometimes the content of a subject’s experience is shaped by facts external to him. This might suggest the following view: what it is for a subject to represent the world in a certain way just is for him to be connected to, or embedded in, his environment in a certain way. But then it might seem that we can advance a stronger claim than the bare externalist one above; perhaps it’s not just the case that some contents of experience fail to supervene on intrinsic properties, but that all such contents fail to supervene on intrinsic properties of perceivers. This is the move from what I have been calling ‘externalism’ to what Egan and John call ‘strong externalism.’ We can express it like this:

For any content of experience p, a subject A could be having an experience with content p even though A’s molecule-for-molecule duplicate, A*, is not having an experience with content p.

Let’s suppose that this is true. Then one might think that this makes plausible the idea that ‘content inversion’ is possible. This is the idea that two people can be inverted with respect to the contents of their experience; so when if when I am in intrinsic state I I am representing o as red, then when Invert is in state I, he is representing o as green. (It is important top see that this is different from the usual spectrum inversion cases, which are inversions in phenomenal character, not in content.)

Let’s suppose that this is possible. Then we argue as follows:

1. At t1, Nonvert (a normal subject) has intrinsic properties I, and is representing o as red.
2. Invert also has intrinsic properties I, and is representing o as green. (Possible by strong externalism)
3. At t2, Nonvert has an experience which represents o as green.
4. Invert’s experience and Nonvert’s experience at t2 have the same content. (2,3)
5. If two experiences have the same content, then they have the same phenomenal character. (Minimal intentionalism)
6. Invert’s experience and Nonvert’s experience at t2 have the same phenomenal character. (4,5)
7. Invert’s experiences at t1 and t2 have different phenomenal characters. (1,3)
8. Invert’s experience and Nonvert’s experience at t1 have different phenomenal characters. (6,7)
9. Invert and Nonvert at t1 have the same intrinsic properties. (1,2)
10. If two agents are in the same intrinsic state, then their experiences have the same phenomenal character. (Internalism about phenomenal character)
11. Invert and Nonvert at t1 are having experiences with the same phenomenal character. (9,10)


C. Invert’s and Nonvert’s experiences at t1 have both the same and distinct phenomenal characters. (8,11)

A key strength of this argument is that it does not rely on biconditional intentionalism; but deduces a contradiction from strong externalism and internalism about phenomenal character with the addition of only minimal intentionalism. One way to read this is as showing that the real culprit in these kinds of cases is minimal intentionalism, and that trying to solve the problem by switching from biconditional intentionalism to minimal intentionalism is only a temporary stopgap.

This seems wrong to me. Minimal intentionalism does not actually contribute all that much to the above argument. To run the above argument, you don’t even need anything as strong as the possibility of content inversion. The following scenario is already enough to generate a contradiction with internalism about phenomenal character:

There are two subjects, A and B, which are such that when each has intrinsic properties I, A is having an experience with content p, and B is having an experience with content q, such that p/=q. However, A could go on to have an experience with content q. If he did, it would match B’s in phenomenology, and be different in phenomenology from his current experience.

This scenario leads to a contradiction with internalism about phenomenal character if it is metaphysically possible for two subjects A and B to satisfy this description. So, to block a contradiction, given internalism about phenomenal character + the possibility of content-inversion, we need something much stronger than the negation of intentionalism, which, as applied to the case of content inversion, says

[] E x E y (x and y are content-inverted --> the phenomenal characters of x and y’s experiences sometimes differ when the contents of their experiences are the same)

Rather, we need the following claim:

[] A x A y (x and y are color-content-inverted --> the phenomenal characters of x and y’s experiences always differ when the contents of their experiences are the same)

This isn’t just the negation of intentionalism, which just says that sometimes sameness of content can go with difference of phenomenal character; this says that, in the case of content-inverts, sameness of content must always go with difference of phenomenal character. I do not see any plausibility in this claim.

So what should we say instead? It seems to me like this. Maybe content-inversion is possible, maybe not. We really have no way of knowing at this point. The standard externalist arguments do not support the possibility of content-inversion; if we had a well-supported externalist theory of mental representation which entailed its possibility, then this would be evidence; but we have no well-supported theory of mental representation, externalist or otherwise. But if it is possible, then it seems plausible to me that spectrum inversion among intrinsic duplicates is possible too. But then the problem lies with internalism about phenomenal character, not with intentionalism. So I suggest that the minimal intentionalist should be confident in the truth of the following disjunction:

content inversion is impossible  \/ internalism about phenomenal character is false

but not worry too much about which disjunct makes it true.

4 Conclusions

I have suggested that there is a very plausible position which avoids these arguments. We should hold the following views: