Jacques Maritain Center
: Readings
Neo-Scholasticism.
The Name and its Meaning.
Neo-Scholasticism is the development of the Scholasticism of the Middle
Ages during the latter half of the nineteenth century. It is not merely
the resuscitation of a philosophy long since defunct, but rather a
restatement in our own day of the philosophia perennis which,
elaborated by the Greeks and brought to perfection by the great
medieval teachers, has never ceased to exist even in modern times. It
has some times been called neo-Thomism partly because St. Thomas
Aquinas in the thirteenth century gave to Scholasticism among the
Latins its final form, partly because the idea has gained ground that
only Thomism can infuse vitality into twentieth century scholasticism.
But Thomism is too narrow a term; the system itself is too large and
comprehensive to be expressed by the name of any single exponent. This
article will deal with the elements which neo-Scholasticism takes over
from the past; the modifications which adapt it to the present; the
welcome accorded it by contemporary thought and the outlook for its
future; its leading representatives and centres; its bibliography.
I. Traditional Elements.
Neo-Scholasticism seeks to restore the fundamental organic doctrines
embodied in the Scholasticism of the thirteenth century. It claims that
philosophy does not vary with each passing phase of history; that the
truth of seven hundred years ago is still true today, and that if the
great medieval thinkers -- Aquinas, Bonaventure, and Duns Scotus --
succeeded in constructing a sound philosophical system on the data
supplied by the Greeks, especially by Aristotle, it must be possible,
in our own day, to gather from the speculation of the Middle Ages the
soul of truth which it contains. These essential conceptions may be
summarized as follows:
(1) God, pure actuality and absolute perfection, is substantially
distinct from every finite thing: he alone can create and preserve all
beings other than Himself. His infinite knowledge includes all that has
been, is, or shall be, and likewise all that is possible.
(2) As to our knowledge of the material world: whatever exists is
itself, an incommunicable, individual substance. To the core of
self-sustaining reality, in the oak-tree for instance, other
realities (accidents) are added -- size, form, roughness, and so on.
All oak-trees are alike, indeed are identical in respect of certain
constituent elements. Considering this likeness and even identity, our
human intelligence groups them into one species and again, in view of
their common characteristics, it ranges various species under one
genus. Such is the Aristotelean solution of the problem of universals
(q.v.). Each substance is in its nature fixed and determined; and
nothing is farther from the spirit of Scholasticism than a theory of
evolution which would regard even the essences of things as products of
change. But this statism requires as its complement a moderate
dynamism, and this is supplied by the central concepts of act and
potency. Whatsoever changes is, just for that reason, limited. The
oak-tree passes through a process of growth, of becoming: whatever is
actually in it now was potentially in it from the beginning. Its vital
functions go on unceasingly (accidental change); but the tree itself
will die, and out of its decayed trunk other substances will come forth
(substantial change). The theory of matter and form is simply an
interpretation of the substantial changes which bodies undergo. The
union of matter and form constitutes the essence of concrete being, and
this essence is endowed with existence. Throughout all change and
becoming there runs a rhythm of finality; the activities of the
countless substances of the universe converge towards an end which is
known to God; finality, in a word, involves optimism.
(3) Man, a compound of body (matter) and of soul (form), puts forth
activities of a higher order -- knowledge and volition. Through his senses
he perceives concrete objects, e.g. this oak; through his intellect he
knows the abstract and universal (the oak). All our intellectual
activity rests on sensory function; but through the active intellect
(intellectus agens) an abstract representation of the sensible object
is provided for the intellectus possibilis. Hence the characteristic of
the idea, its non-materiality, and on this is based the principal
argument for the spirituality and immortality of the soul. Here, too,
is the foundation of logic and of the theory of knowledge, the
justification of our judgments and syllogisms. Upon knowledge follows
the appetitive process, sensory or intellectual according to the sort
of knowledge. The will (appetitus intellectualis) in certain conditions
is free, and thanks to this liberty man is the master of his destiny.
Like all other beings, we have an end to attain and we are morally
obliged, though not compelled, to attain it. Natural happiness would
result from the full development of our powers of knowing and loving.
We should find and possess God in this world since the corporeal world
is the proper object of our intelligence. But above nature is the order
of grace and our supernatural happiness will consist in the direct
intuition of God, the beatific vision. Here philosophy ends and
theology begins.
II. Adaptation to Modern Needs.
The neo-Scholastic programme includes, in the next place, the
adaptation of medieval principles and doctrines to our present
intellectual needs. Complete immobility is no less incompatible with
progress than out-and-out relativism. Vita in motu. To make
Scholasticism rigid and stationary would be fatal to it. The doctrines
revived by the new movement are like an inherited fortune; to refuse it
would be folly, but to manage it without regard to actual conditions
would be worse. With Dr. Ehrhard one may say: "Aquinas should be our
beacon, not our boundary" ("Der Katholicismus und das zwanzigste
Jahrh. im Lichte der Kirchlichen Entwicklung der Neuzeit", Stuttgart,
1902, 252). We have now to pass in review the various factors in the
situation and to see in what respect the new Scholasticism differs from
the old and how far it adapts itself to our age.
(1) Elimination of False or Useless Notions.
Neo-Scholasticism rejects the theories of physics, celestial and
terrestrial, which the Middle Ages grafted on the principles, otherwise
sound enough, of cosmology and metaphysics; e.g. the perfection and
superiority of astral substance, the "incorruptibility" of the heavenly
bodies, their external connexion with "motor spirits", the influence of
the stars on the generation of earthly beings, the four "simple"
bodies, etc. It further rejects those philosophical theories which are
disproved by the results of investigation; e.g. the diffusion of
sensible "species" throughout a medium and their introduction into the
organs of sense. Even the Scholastic ideas that have been retained are
not all of equal importance; criticism and personal conviction may
retrench or modify them considerably, without injury to fundamental
principles.
(2) Study of the History of Philosophy.
The medieval scholars cultivated the history of philosophy solely with
a view to its utility, i.e. as a means of gathering the deposit of
truth contained in the writings of the ancients and, especially, for
the purpose of refuting error and thus emphasizing the value of their
own doctrine. Modern students, on the contrary, regard every human fact
and achievement as in itself significant, and accordingly they treat
the history of philosophy in a spirit that is more disinterested. With
this new attitude, neo-Scholasticism is in full sympathy; it does its
share in the work of historical reconstruction by employing critical
methods; it does not attempt to condense the opinions of others into a
syllogism and refute them with a phrase, nor does it commend the
practice of putting whole systems into a paragraph or two in order to
annihilate them with epithet or invective. Neo-Scholasticism, however,
does not confine its interest to ancient and medieval philosophy; its
chief concern is with present-day systems. It takes issue with them and
offsets their theories of the world by a synthesis of its own. It is
only by keeping in touch with actual living thought that it can claim a
place in the twentieth century and command the attention of its
opponents. And it has everything to gain from a discussion in which it
encounters Positivism, Kantism, and other forms or tendencies of modern
speculation.
(3) Cultivation of the Sciences.
The need of a philosophy based on science is recognized to-day by every
school. Neo-Scholasticism simply follows the example of the Aristotelean
and medieval philosophy in taking the data of research as the
groundwork of its speculation. That there are profound differences
between the Middle Ages and modern times from the scientific point of
view, is obvious. One has only to consider the multiplication of the
sciences in special lines, the autonomy which science as a whole has
acquired, and the clear demarcation established between popular views
of nature and their scientific interpretation. But it is equally plain
that neo-Scholasticism must follow up each avenue of investigation,
since it undertakes, as Aristotle and Aquinas did, to provide a
synthetic explanation of phenomena by referring them to their ultimate
causes and determining their place in the universal order of things;
and this undertaking, if the synthesis is to be deep and comprehensive,
presupposes a knowledge of the details furnished by each science. It is
not possible to explain the world of phenomena while neglecting the
phenomena that make up the world. "All that exists, as contemplated by
the human mind, forms one large system or complex fact. . . . Like a
short-sighted reader, its eye pores closely, and travels slowly, over
the awful volume which lies open for its inspection. . . . These
various partial views or abstractions . . . are called sciences . . .
they proceed on the principle of a division of labour. . . . And
further the comprehension of the bearings of one science on another,
and the use of each to each, and the location of them all, with one
another, this belongs, I conceive, to a sort of science distinct from
all of them, and in some sense, a science of sciences, which is my own
conception of what is meant by philosophy" (Newman, "Idea of a
Univesity", Discourse III, iii, iv, 44 sqq.). There is, of course, the
pedagogical problem; how shall philosophy maintain its control over the
ever-widening field of the various sciences? In reply, we may cite the
words of Cardinal Mercier, a prominent leader in the neo-Scholastic
movement: "As a matter of fact", he declares, "the difficulty is a
serious one, and one may say in general terms, that it is not going to
be solved by any one man. As the domain of fact and observation grows
larger and larger, individual effort becomes less competent to survey
and master it all: hence the necessity of co-operative effort to supply
what is lacking in the work of isolated investigators; hence too the
need of union between the synthetic mind and the analytic, in order to
secure, by daily contact and joint action, the harmonious development
of philosophy and science". ("La philosophie néo-scholastique" in
"Revue néo-scholastique", 1894, 17).
(4) Innovations in Doctrinal Matters.
Once it turned its attention to modern fashions of thought,
neo-Scholasticism found itself face to face with problems of which
medieval philosophy had not the slightest suspicion or at any rate did
not furnish a solution. It had to bear the brunt of conflict between
its own principles and those of the systems in vogue, especially of
Positivism and Criticism. And it had to take up, from its own point of
view, the questions which are favourite topics of discussion in the
schools of our time. How far then, one may ask, has neo-Scholasticism
been affected by modern thought? First of all, as to metaphysics: in
the Middle Ages its claim to validity met with no challenge, whereas,
in the twentieth century, its very possibility is at stake and, to
defend it against the concerted attack of Hume and Kant and Comte, the
true significance of such concepts as being, substance, absolute,
cause, potency, and act must be explained and upheld. It is further
needful to show that, in a very real sense, God is not unknowable; to
rebut the charges preferred by Herbert Spencer against the traditional
proofs of God's existence; to deal with the materials furnished by
ethnography and the history of religions; and to study the various
forms which monism and immanentism nowadays assume. Cosmology can well
afford to insist on the traditional theory of matter and form, provided
it pay due attention to the findings of physics, chemistry,
crystallography, and mineralogy, and meet the objections of atomism and
dynamism, theories which, in the opinion of scientific authority, are
less satisfactory as explanations of natural phenomena than the
hylomorphism (q.v.) of the Scholastics. The theory also of qualities,
once the subject of ridicule, is nowadays endorsed by some of the most
prominent scientists. In psychology especially the progressive spirit
of neo-Scholasticism makes itself felt. The theory of the substantial
union of body and soul, as an interpretation of biological, psychical,
and psycho-physiological facts, is far more serviceable than the
extreme spiritualism of Descartes on the one hand and the Positivism of
modern thinkers on the other. As Wundt admits, the results of
investigation in physiological psychology do not square either with
materialism or with dualism whether of the Platonic or of the Cartesian
type; it is only Aristotelean animism, which brings psychology into
connexion with biology, that can offer a satisfactory metaphysical
interpretation of experimental psychology ("Grundzüge d. physiol.
Psychologie", II, 540). So vigorous indeed has been the growth of
psychology that each of its offshoots is developing in its own way:
such is the case with criteriology, aesthetics, didactics, pedagogy, and
the numerous ramifications of applied psychology. Along these various
lines, unknown to medieval philosophy, neo-Scholasticism is working
energetically and successfully. Its criteriology is altogether new: the
older Scholasticism handled the problem of certitude from the deductive
point of view; God could not have misshaped the faculties with which He
endowed the mind in order that it might attain to knowledge.
Neo-Scholasticism, on the other hand, proceeds by analysis and
introspection it states the problem in the terms which, since Kant's
day, are the only admissible terms, but as against the Kantian
criticism it finds the solution in a rational dogmatism. Its aesthetics
holds a middle course between the extreme subjectivism of many modern
thinkers who would reduce the beautiful to a mere impression, and the
no less extreme objectivism which the Greeks of old maintained. It is
equally at home in thc field of experimental psychology which
investigates the correlation between conscious phenomena and their
physiological accompaniments; in fact, its theory of the substantial
union of body and soul implies as its corollary a "bodily resonance"
corresponding to each psychical process. The laws and principles which
the modern science of education has drawn from experience find their
adequate explanation in neo-Scholastic doctrine; thus, the intuitive
method, so largely accepted at present as an essential element in
education, is based on the Scholastic theory that nothing enters the
intellect save through the avenue of sense. In the study of ethical
problems, neo-Scholasticism holds fast to the vital teachings that
prevailed in the thirteenth century, but at the same time it takes into
account the historical and sociological data which explain the varying
application of principles in successive ages. In view of contemporary
systems which, on a purely experimental basis, attempt to set aside all
moral imperatives and ideas of value, it is necessary to insist on the
older concepts of good and evil, of finality and obligation -- a need
which is easily supplied by neo-Scholastic ethics. As to logic, the
most perfect part of Aristotle's great constructive work and therefore
that which has been least modified in the course of time. Its positions
still call for defence against the objections of writers like Mill, who
regard the syllogism as a "solemn farce". Accordingly, with due
consideration for modern modes of thinking, neo-Scholasticism adapts
the teaching of the Middle Ages to actual conditions. Even as regards
the relations between philosophy and religion, there are important
changes to note. For the medieval mind in the Western world, philosophy
and theology were identical until about the twelfth century. In the
thirteenth the line of demarcation was clearly drawn, but philosophy
was still treated as the preliminary training for theology. This is no
longer the case; neo-Scholasticism assigns to philosophy a value of its
own as a rational explanation of the world, on a par in this respect
with Positivism and other systems; and it welcomes all who are bent on
honest research, whether their aim be purely philosophical or
apologetic. Parallel with these modifications are those which affect
the pedagogical phase of the movement. The methods of teaching
philosophy in the thirteenth century were too closely dependent on the
culture of that age; hence they have been replaced by modern
procedures, curricula, and means of propagation. It would be
ill-advised to wrap neo-Scholastic doctrine in medieval envelopes, e.g.
to write books on the plan of the theological "Summae" or the "Quodlibetal
Questions" that were current in the thirteenth century. Without at all
lessening its force, syllogistic demonstration gains in attractiveness
when its essential characteristics are retained and clothed about with
modern forms of presentation. In this connexion, the use of living
languages as a means of exposition has obvious advantages and finds
favour with many of those who are best qualified to judge.
III. Appreciation.
By interesting itself in modern questions, interpreting the results of
scientific research and setting forth its principles for thorough
discussion, neo-Scholasticism has compelled attention: it has to be
reckoned with. Among non-Catholics, many leaders of thought have
frankly acknowledged that its methods and doctrines deserve to be
examined anew. Men like Boutroux admit that Aristotle's system may well
serve as an offset to Kantism and evolution (Aristote, Etudes
d'histoire et de philosophie, Paris, 1901, 202). Paulsen ("Kant der
Philosoph des Protestantismus" in "Kantstudien", 1899) and Eucken
("Thomas von Aquino u. Kant, Ein Kampf zweier Welten", loc. cit., 1901)
declare that neo-Thomism is the rival of Kantism and that the conflict
between them is the "clash of two worlds". Harnack ("Lehrbuch d.
Dogmengesch.", III, 3rd. ed., 327), Seeberg ("Realencyklopädie f.
Prot. Theol." 5. v. "Scholastik") and others protest against those who
underrate the value of scholastic doctrine. Among Catholics,
neo-Scholasticism gains ground day by day. It is doing away with
Ontologism, Traditionalism, the Dualism of Gunther, and the exaggerated
Spiritualism of Descartes. It is free from the weaknesses of Pragmatism
and Voluntarism, systems in which some thinkers have vainly sought the
reconciliation of their philosophy and their faith. Neo-Scholasticism
has a character of permanence as truth itself has; but it is destined
in its development to keep up with scientific progress. Like everything
that lives, it must advance; arrested growth would mean decay.
IV. The Leaders and their Work.
The neo-Scholastic movement was inaugurated by such writers as
Sanseverino (1811-65) and Cornoldi (1822-92) in Italy; Gonzalez (1831-
92) in Spain; Kleutgen (1811-83) and Stöckl (1823-95) in Germany; de
San (1832-1904), Dupont, and Lepidi in Belgium; Farges and Dormet de
Vorges (1910) in France, who with other scholars carried on the work
of restoration before the Holy See gave it solemn approval and
encouragement. Pius IX, it is true, in various letters, recognized its
importance; but it was the encyclical "AEterni Patris" of Leo XIII
(4 Aug., 1879) that imparted to neo-Scholasticism its definitive
character and quickened its development. This document sets forth the
principles by which the movement is to be guided in a progressive
spirit, and by which the medieval doctrine is to take on new life in
its modern environment. "If," says the pope, "there be anything that
the Scholastic doctors treated with excessive subtlety or with
insufficient consideration, or that is at variance with well founded
teachings of later date, or is otherwise improbable, we by no means
intend that it shall be proposed to our age for imitation. . . . We
certainly do not blame those learned and energetic men who turn to the
profit of philosophy their own assiduous labours and erudition as well
as the results of modern investigation; for we are fully aware that all
this goes to the advancement of knowledge." In Italy, the movement was
vigorous from the start. The Accademia di San Tommaso, founded in
1874, published, up to 1891, a review entitled "La Scienza Italiana".
Numerous works were produced by Zigliara (1833-93), Satolli (1839-
1909), Liberatore (1810-92), Barberis (1847-96), Schiffini (1841-
1906), de Maria, Talamo, Lorenzelli, Ballerini, Matussi, and others.
The Italian writers at first laid special emphasis on the metaphysical
features of Scholasticism, without paying sufficient attention to the
sciences or to the history of philosophy. Recently, however, this
situation has undergone a change which promises excellent results.
From Italy the movement spread into the other European countries and
found supporters in Germany such as Kleutgen, Stöckl, the authors of
the "Philosophia Lacensis", published at Maria Laach by the Jesuits
(Pesch, Hontheim, Cathrein), Gutberlet, Commer, Willmann, Kaufmann,
Glossner, Grabmann, and Schneid. These scholars have made valuable
contributions to the history of philosophy, especially that of the
Middle Ages. Stöckl led the way with his "Geschichte d. Philosophie
des Mittelalters" (Mainz, 1864-66). Ehrle and Denifle (q.v.) founded
in 1885 the "Archiv für Literatur u. Kirchengesch. d. Mittelalters",
and the latter edited the monumental "Chartularium" of the University
of Paris. In 1891, Von Hertling and Bäumker began the publication of
their "Beiträge zur Gesch. d. Phil. des Mittelalters". Belgium has
been particularly favoured. Leo XIII established (1891) at Louvain the
"Institut de philosophie" for the special purpose of teaching the
doctrine of St. Thomas together with history and the natural sciences.
The Institute was placed in charge of Mgr (now Cardinal) Mercier whose
"Cours de philosophie" has been translated into the principal languages
of Europe. In France, besides those already mentioned, Vallet,
Gardair, Fonsegrive, and Piat have taken a prominent part in the
movement; in Holland (Amsterdam) de Groot; in Switzerland (Freiburg),
Mandonnet; in Spain, Orti y Lara, Urráburu, Gómez Izquierdo; in Mexico,
Garcia; in Brazil, Santroul; in Hungary, Kiss and Pecsi; in England,
Clarke, Maher, John Rickaby, Joseph Rickaby, Boedder (Stonyhurst
Series); in the United States, Coppens, Poland, Brother Chrysostom, and
the professors at the Catholic University (Shanahan, Turner, and Pace).
Neo-Scholasticism has been endorsed by four Catholic Congresses: Paris
(1891); Brussels (1895); Freiburg (1897); Munich (1900). A considerable
number of reviews have served as its exponents: "Divus Thomas" (1879-
1903); "Rivista Italiana di filosofia neo-scolastica" (Florence, since
1909); "Annales de Philosophie Chrétienne" (Paris, since 1830); "Revue
néo-scolastique de Philosophie" (Louvain, since 1894); "Revue de
Philosophie" (Paris, since 1900);" Revue des Sciences philosophiques
et théologiques" (Kain, Belgium, since 1907); "Revue Thomiste" (Paris,
since 1893); "Philosophisches Jahrbuch für Philosophie und
spekulative Theologie" (Paderborn, since 1887); "St. Thomas Blätter"
(Ratisbon, since 1888); Bölcseleti-Folyóirat (Budapest, since 1886);"
Revista Lulliana" (Barcelona, since 1901);" Cienza Tomista" (Madrid,
since 1910). In addition to these, various periodical publications not
specially devoted to philosophy have given neo-Scholasticism their
cordial support.
Various commentaries on the Encyclical AEterni Patris:
VAN WEDDINGEN, L'Encyclique de S.S. Leo XIII et la restauration de la philosophie chrétienne (Brussels, 1880);
SCHNEID, Die Philosophie des hl. Thomas und ihre Bedeutung für die Gegenwart (Würzburg, 1881);
ROYCE, Pope Leo's philosophical movement and its relations to modern thought in Rev. Cath. Pedag. (1903);
MERCIER, Les origines de la psychologie contemporaine (2nd ed., Louvain, 1908);
DE WULF, Scholasticism old and new, an introduction to scholastic philosophy, medieval and modern, tr. COFFEY (Dublin, 1907);
IDEM, Introduction à la philosophie néo-scolastique (Louvain and Paris, 1904);
PERRIER, The Revival of Scholastic Philosophy in the Nineteenth Century (New York, 1909);
Le mouvement néo-thomiste, periodical bulletin published in Revue néo-scolastique de Philosophie (Louvain);
SANTROUL, Was ist neu-scholastische Philosophie (Münster, 1909);
GARCIA, Tomismo y neo thomismo (San Lois Potosi, 1905);
TALAMO, Il rinnovamento del pensiero tomistico e la scienza moderna (Siena, 1878);
FRISCHKOPF, Die Psychologie der neuen Löwener Schule (Lucerne, 1908);
BESSE, Deux centres du mouvement thomiste, Rome et Louvain (Louvain, 1902);
TELZER, L'Institut supérieur de philosophie 1590-1904 (Louvain, 1904);
HABRICH, Die neu-scholastioche Philosophie der Loewener Schule, introduction to German tr. of MERCIER, Psychologie (Kempten, 1906);
COFFEY, Philosophy and the Sciences at Louvain, Appendix to DE WULF's Scholasticism Old and New;
ARNAIZ MARCELLIUO, El Institute superior de fliosofia en la universidad católica de Lovaina (Madrid, 1901);
VAN BECELAERE, La philosophie en Amérique depuis les origines jusqu'á nos jours (New York, 1904);
BLANC, Histoire de la philosophie et particulièrement de la philosophie contemporaine, III (Lyons, 1896);
EUCKEN, Neuthomismus und die neuere Wissessschaft in Philosoph. Monatshefte (1888);
IDEM, Thomas van Aquino und Kant. Ein Kampf zweier Welten in Kantstudien (1901);
IDEM, Das Wissenschaftliches Centurum des heutigen Thomismus (Munich, 1904);
GÓMEZ IZQUIERDO in Rivista di Aragon (1903);
CONDE, Una excursión filosófica par España in Revista ibero-americana (1902);
MERCIER, Discours d'ouverture du cours de philosophie de S. Thomas (Louvain, 1882);
PACE, St. Thomas and Modern Thought in Cath. Univ. Bulletin (1896);
PICAVET, Le mouvement néo-thomiste in Revue Philosophique (1892; 1896; 1902);
VIEL, Le mouvement thomiste au XIXe siècle in Revue Thomiste (1909 and 1910);
The Value of Scholastic Philosophy, Judgment of a special Committee of the Privy council of Ireland after Pleadings and evidence learned on October 13-15, 1909 (Dublin, 1909);
MAHER, Psychology (London and New York, 1905);
JOYCE, Principles of Logic (London and New York, 1908).
M. DE WULF.