The idea of creation is deeply connected with the religions of the Book and, particularly, with all Christian dogmas. At first sight the concept of creation seems to be less immediate, but deeper than monism. In fact the idea of creation suggests that there is something else, or rather Someone else at the very root of the universe: can we actually think that there is not anything else (that there is only the universe)? It is noteworthy that when speaking of God as something else or someone else, ontologically different from the universe (transcendence of God), I do not mean something spatially outside the world, but, rather, the very depth of reality which penetrates everything (immanence of God). From this point of view the idea of creation suggests that what is more perfect in our everyday experience (the personal dimension) must be - in an analogous form - at the very root of reality. Nowadays we need to rethink creation, because the scientific picture of the universe has changed very much in this century and very few important books have been written on this subject from the philosophical and metaphysical point of view during the latter years.
In my opinion there are no strong scientific objections against the idea of creation (although sometimes it might seem that there are), nor indeed can there be, because science and metaphysics play different roles. Although we often come across scientific theories that seem to be either sympathetic to the concept of creation (such as the "inflationary universe of the big-bang theory") or not (such as the "quantum cosmology"{5}), nevertheless the idea of creation can neither be proved nor falsified by scientific means. I think that the real objections to the concept of creation have a metaphysical and ethical basis in a kind of implicit metaphysics and ethics of every man and, particularly, of scientists, whose starting point might also be scientific theories.
Therefore, let us now consider what the meaning of creation is, which are the main conditions for thinking of it and which difficulties and facilities we find nowadays in trying to think of it. We shall see that the difficulties facing creation are, basically, the difficulties facing theism.
God is simple as he is Spirit, but not as we are spirit. He transcends in his simplicity the material as well the spiritual dimension of our world.
Aquinas holds that, taken as a whole, creation may be considered either from the active point of view of God or from the passive point of view of a creature. If we look at it from the former point of view, creation means the action of God that is his essence together with his relationship to creature (which is not a real relationship, but only a conceptual one). Instead, if we intend it from the latter point of view, creation is "a certain relationship to God together with the newness of being (novitas essendi)"{11}.
As he creates the world and maintains it in existence, God is transcendent and immanent towards the world. He is immanent as he is transcendent. A naive idea of God's transcendence comes up with the criticism of Hegel according to whom infinity, if considered on the same level of finite beings, becomes itself finite. On the contrary, since the pure Act of existing absolutely transcends the world, he can also be immanent in the world or, rather, the world may be "in God". In fact only what is ontologically different (not only on the level of a spatial transcendence) is able to actually penetrate something ontologically different. From this point of view, the idea of creation, if conceived according to its main principles, saves the main demands of pantheistic monism or acosmism: the transcendent God manifests himself in the world and by the world: the world is a manifestation of God. According to Aquinas, He is immediately (immediate) and intimately (intime) present in every creature{12}. Creating, knowing and loving the creatures coincide in God. Although a creature would be absolutely nothing without the creative causality of God, still the creature actually has its own being and its own causality. Far more than monism, creationism saves also the instance of the autonomous causality of creatures and, therefore, of scientific knowledge{13}.
Some contemporary thinkers use human language, which Thomas uses particularly when dealing with communication within the Trinity, when attempting to describe creation: as words are a novelty (novum ) that manifests immediately man's thought, so, in creating the world, God's will immediately is made manifest{15}. But there are important differences: first of all since God is simple, there is no difference between Him and his action (creation). In fact it does not add anything to Him. The world manifests immediately God's act, that is his very Being-Acting. Secondly, human language is not created, because it depends on our previous experience of the world. The same is the case of other so called "creative" human works such as composing music, painting a picture and so on. "Creation" here means something very different from God's creation, although the former can help us in thinking of the latter. To sum up: in order to think of the act of creation, we have to use the concept of efficient causality, but we must consider it from the point of view of human intentional acts, and then we must reread both in an analogous sense: God transcends any other form of causality. He is not the first cause of a chain of causes.
As we can see, God's omnipotence is not sufficient if we want to explain creation: it is a necessary, but not a sufficient condition. If the Absolute, that is transcendent, is not Intelligence and Love, if He is not a "personal" God and therefore if He is not free, creation remains incomprehensible: why should God have created the world, as He does not need anything? Therefore from this point of view the world exists because God creates, knows and loves it in the same act: being is a gift. But we cannot conceive Goodness, Love, Truth beyond being: they would not be at all. Only if God is the Omnipotent Being and at the same time Intelligence, Good-Love, Person , we can actually think of creation.
We must stress the freedom of God in creating because of our being unable to transcend personal perfection (we cannot think of something more perfect than a person, despite the limits of the human person){16} as well as for our need of preserving the absoluteness of God, which would be questioned by any necessary modality of deriving the world from the Absolute. This is the case of every kind of emanationism. A God from whom the world came out necessarily would be necessarily dependent upon the world that He creates, therefore no longer "absolute" (according to the Latin etymology of the term{17}). Therefore we need to use the concept of creation in order to preserve both the reality of God and the reality of the world. The fact that God is free in creating means also that He can, if He wants, "contain his omnipotence" (speaking from a very human point of view), causing also very small effects{18}. This is, classically, the case of miracles, which are not interventions from outside creation{19}. The potency and the perfection of the Creator is not apparent only by the greatness of his effects, but also by their smallness, that means by the spiritual character of his act. Moreover, since the personal and free God is trustworthy, as Aquinas affirms, He maintains in its being the world that creates: creation and conservation of the world are the same act.
Also the anthropic principle needs an Intelligence at the root of the universe. And this is not all: the evolution of the scientific concept of matter during this century has changed the cartesian and modern concept of the strong spirit- matter opposition, which should therefore be reconsidered. The new concept of matter probably supports more easily a creationist interpretation of the universe, because it can be considered permeable by the divine potency.
Nowadays the difficulties in rethinking creation, which lead us to assume a more or less implicitly monistic type of metaphysics, are the same difficulties in rethinking theism and do not seem to have first of all scientific roots. On the contrary they seem to have pre scientific, cultural and philosophical roots{23}. . I shall attempt to consider these epistemic obstacles and to answer them.
Perhaps the difficulty or discouragement in thinking of God as the starting point of everything is deeply connected with the difficulty in conceiving beings as actuated by the act of existing (ontological experience - cfr. 6) and principally in conceiving a human person as plenitude and fulfilment. In fact we do not know other experiences of perfection greater than those of the act of existing, which causes the origin of everything including that of a person (actuated and unified by his substantial form-soul). The act of existing as perfection becomes more apparent to us particularly by the symbolical experience of things and mainly by the experience of human person. In a symbol the individual and the universal are, from a certain point of view, the same{31}. Everything - a tree, a house, the moon an so on - may acquire a symbolic dimension in our experience, making us think by means of analogy of the plenitude of being, because everything is actuated by the act of existing. Otherwise knowing the uniqueness of a person and of his acts is looking at a concrete, although contingent infinity, because the human person can know and desire anything: he is a microcosm. Therefore our mother, our friends may acquire a symbolic meaning. The very source of both the experiences of the act of existing and of "person" is the experience of ourselves as existing, living and intelligent, hierarchically compound and actuated by the act of existing beings ("persons"). It is noteworthy that the experience of ourselves is deeply connected with our experience of the world as a whole (that means with our perception of the greatness of the sky, of the mountains, of the sea).
In particular: the act of existing, as it actuates every being and every essence or perfection, can make every other perfection infinite (and also that kind of perfection that is a human person){32}. We can find here the source of the idea of the God of theism. To sum up: the experience of the act of existing and the experience of "person" as something unified by form are deeply connected in our thinking of perfection and of God as actual infinity.
Finally it is noteworthy that in the Christian religious experience of western societies Christ and the sacraments of the Church are the main symbols of the Actual infinity of God. It is not amazing that the obscuration of this peculiar religious experience may be nowadays an important cause of our difficulty in conceiving the infinity and simplicity of God.
We must consider also that in post modernity the idea of an infinite God seems to set a limit to the human freedom of interpreting the world and its life (infinity of hermeneutics) and of choosing as he/she likes a certain way of life (ethical relativism){33}. From this point of view the concept of an infinite potentiality (bad infinity - for instance the idea of infinite universes in contemporary cosmology) or even the idea of a finite whole (an universe unbounded, but finite){34}easily becomes a way to implicitly refuse the idea of a Designer of the universe (God) and also a surrogate for the actual infinity of God, of which nowadays we seldom make experience, about which we are not used to reflect and that we may consider cause of violence and of alienation. Therefore I believe that there are not first of all scientific, but ontological, anthropologic, ethical and religious reasons for our difficulty to acknowledge that there is an Actual infinity, which is God, who creates the world.
Since it is difficult to think of a universe without rationality, because of the order we can find in it, sometimes it happens that we conceive an impersonal reason as the root of that order (Spinoza, Einstein, many scientists). But is it meaningful to think of an impersonal reason? Is it actually conceivable by us?{36} Or is it like a round square? As Stephen Davis writes: "Transcendence, in at least one sense, does seem to be indicated by the evidence of design. It is hard to see how a being that is a part of the process of nature and is subject to its law can account for them or be said to have organised (let alone created) them. If a given being is the universe's designer, I would take that to entail that being cannot be identified with any thing, event, or process that exists or occurs in the physical world. And if that much is true, it also seems to follow that the designer of the universe must be non-physical or incorporeal (which is of course one of the crucial attributes of God)"{37}.
I believe that we conceive an impersonal reason when we believe that mere materialism is not enough, but we do not want to become theists. That often happens because of an irrational fear of anthropomorphism in thinking of God{38}. In fact, in my opinion -but it is also the opinion of classical philosophy - we cannot have a more perfect experience than that of the act of existing that actuates our beings. And we cannot make experience of more perfect acts (that means more complex and unified - more "simple" in the classical sense) than those that are typically human. But to conceive an impersonal God, although it might seem a more purified concept of the Divinity, nevertheless means to fall into a concept of the Absolute more reductionist than that which is proper of theism, a concept shaped on the material and quantitative dimension of reality, that we perceive by sense-perception rather than on the objects of contemporary science. Augustine stressed this risk against Manicheism. Perhaps nowadays we can find new forms of Manicheism. Therefore instead of conceiving God as super-personal, we conceive Him as sub-personal, contradicting our everyday experience of order and hierarchy which requires a transcendent reason as the cause of that order{39}: "Pantheist and Christian also agree that God is super-personal . The Christian mean by this that God has a positive structure which we could never have guessed in advance, any more than a knowledge of squares would have enabled us to guess at a cube. But we can at least comprehend our incomprehension, and see that if there is something beyond personality it ought to be incomprehensible in that sort of way. The Pantheist, on the other hand, though he may say 'super personal' really conceives God in terms of what is sub personal - as though the Flatlanders thought a cube existed in fewer dimensions than a square"{40}.
In fact there is a risk of stressing in our idea of the world and of ourselves a frame connected with sense perception and technology instead of a frame connected with our original personal experience of ourselves as living and understanding beings{41}. But the latter kind of frame (everyday knowledge) is the very background also of science itself. As it has been noted: "Modern science has for long time overlooked the fact that the individual can be known only within the framework of a universal model. This is due to the fact that scientific inquiry does not start from nothing, but from everyday knowledge, which already singles out individual objects and events thanks to the intervention of certain universals...there is no moment in which our knowledge can dispense with the universal, whether it be because we need the "unity of the multiplicity", or because we must be able to grasp "the permanent in the mutable"{42}. From this point of view "the metaphysical realist of Aristotelian-Thomistic persuasion is not concerned to deny that one can adopt a variety of ontologies, or that there is a variety of categories of things. Equally he or she should resist such phrases as such the world "forces us to think of it in a single integrated way'. That is both literally false and liable on interpretation to induce scientific reductionism. There are many 'things' and 'ways of being'. Nonetheless, among these some (those with objective principles of unity) are more substantial than others"{43}. We call them, hierarchically, mere substances, living beings and intelligent beings ("persons"). What makes this a hierarchy, rather than a mere list, is that the latter types of organism have all the powers of the former, but not viceversa{44}.
Although the concepts of God and of creation transcend our human experience, they are deeply connected with our perception of the ontological hierarchy of beings and with the supremacy of that "whole" which is man. Theism is strongly connected with humanism.
1 J.J. Haldane in J.J.C. Smart and J.J. Haldane, Atheism and Theism, Blackwell, Oxford 1996, p. 195.
2 Cfr. M. P. Lévine, Pantheism. A Non-Theistic Coception of Divinity, Routledge, London and New York 1994; Pantheism, "The Monist", vol. 80, no. 2, 1997.
3 Cfr. C.S. Lewis, Miracles. A Preliminary Study, The Macmillan Company, New York 1973, p. 84: "Pantheism is congenial to our minds not because it is the final stage in a slow process of enlightenment, but because it is almost as old as we are".
4 C.S. Lewis, cit., p. 86. See also Augustine, De vera religione, XX, 40; XLIX, 96.
5 Cfr. the 'quantum tunneling from nothing' described by E. Tryon, A. Vilenkin and A. Guth and the cosmology of S. Hawking. Cf., for instance, A. Vilenkin, Creation of Universes from Nothing, "Physics Letters" B 117 (1982), pp. 25-28; Quantum Origin of the Universe, "Nuclear Physics", B252 (1985), pp. 141-152.. Cf. S. Hawking, A Brief History of Time (New York: Bantam Books, 1988. On these subjects cf. C.J. Isham, "Quantum Theories of the Creation of the Universe" and Robert John Russell, "Finite Creation without a Beginning. The Doctrine of Creation in Relation to Big Bang and Quantum Cosmologies" in Quantum Cosmology and the Laws of Nature, edited by Robert J. Russell, Nancey Murphy, and C.J. Isham (Vatican City: Vatican Observatory Publications, 1993), pp. 49-89, 293-329.
6 Cfr. W. E. Carroll, Thomas Aquinas and Big-Bang Cosmology, in Proceedings of the Summer Thomistic Institute 1997, Notre Dame University Press, Notre Dame (Indiana) (in press): "Despite the claims of some contemporary theorists that, properly speaking, we can get something from nothing, those theories of the Big Bang which employ insights from particle physics, concerning vacuum fluctuations, are consistent with the ancient principle that you cannot get something from nothing. The 'vacuum' of modern particle physics, whose 'fluctuation' supposedly brings our universe into existence, is not absolutely nothing. It is only no thing like our present universe, but it is still something. How else could 'it' fluctuate? Thus, we need to recognize that frequently the 'nothing' discussed by contemporary cosmologists is not absolutely nothing. Yet it is this latter sense of nothing which is crucial to the traditional doctrine of creation out of nothing".
7 De pot. III, 4 sed c.
8 According to Thomas God can create contingent and necessary beings. Cf CG. II, 30: "Esse autem necesse simpliciter non repugnat ad rationem esse creati: nihil enim prohibet aliquid esse necesse quod tamen suae necessitatis causam habet...".
9 See J. Lamont, Aquinas on Divine Simplicity, "The Monist", vol. 80, no. 4, 1977, pp. 521-538.
10Fewer analogies are to be found in XVII-XIX century physics and cosmology.
11 Cfr. De pot. III, 3. Cf. ST. I, 45, 3.
12 Cfr. De ver. VII, 8, 16 ad 12: "...ipse Deus est propria et immediata causa uniucuiusque rei, et quodammodo magis intima cuique quam ipsum sit intimum sibi, ut Augustinus dicit". Cf. A. Campodonico, Il carattere imediato della presenza di Dio nel mondo secondo Tommaso d'Aquino, "Rivista di filosofia neo-scolastica", 76, 1984, 2, p. 245-268.
13 Cf. De pot. III, 8.
14 Cfr. De pot. III, 1 ad 6: "Sicut vero intelligere principia, quod est concludendi principium, non est ex aliquo ex quo concludatur, ita creatio, quae est omnis motus principium, non est ex aliquo"; III, 8 ad 3: "Infusio tamen gratiae accedit ad rationem creationis in quantum gratia non habet causam in subiecto, nec efficientem, nec talem materiam in qua sit hoc modo in potentia, quod per agens naturale educi possit in actum, sicut est de aliis formis naturalibus"; ST. I, 21, 4: " Opus autem divinae iustitiae semper praesupponit opus misericordiae et in eo fundatur. Creaturae enim non debetur aliquid nisi , nsis propter aliquid in eo praexistens, vel praeconsideratum: et rursus, si illud creaturae debetur, hoc erit propter aliquid prius. Et cum non sit procedere in infinitum, oportet devenire ad aliquid quod ex sola bonitate divinae voluntatis dependeat, quae est ultimus finis. Utpote si dicamus quod habere manus debitum est homini propter animam rationalem; animam vero rationalem habere, ad hoc quod sit homo; hominem vero esse, propter divinam bonitatem. Et sic in quolibet opere Dei apparet misericordia, quantum ad primam radicem eius". On the relationship between generation and creation, necessity and freedom in God cf. De pot. II, 3, in particular II, 6 ad 1: "Potentia autem generandi, secundum quod natura inclinat, agit. Hoc autem non facit diversitatem potentiae, nam nihil prohibet aliquam potentiam ad aliquem actum imperari a voluntate et ad alium inclinari a natura. Sicut intellectus noster ad credendum inclinatur a voluntate, ad intelligendum prima principia ducitur ex natura".
15 Cfr. M.H.E. Henstenberg, Sein und Ursprünglichkeit zur philosophischen Grundlegung der Shöpfunglehre, München-Salzburg-Köln 1959.
16 Cfr. De pot. I, 5, particularly: "Impossibile est autem, id quod agit ex naturae necessitate sibi ipsi determinare finem: quia quod est tale, est ex se agens; et quod est agens vel motum ex se ipso, in ipso est agere vel non agere, moveri vel non moveri, ut dicitur VIII Physic., et hoc non potest competere ei quod ex +necessitate movetur, cum sit determinatum ad unum. Unde oportet quod omni ei quod agit ex necessitate naturae, determinetur finis ab aliquod quod sit intelligens. Propter quod dicitur a Philosophis, quod opus naturae est opus intelligentiae. Unde si aliquando aliquod corpus naturale adiungitur alicui intellectui, sicut in homine patet, quantum ad illas actiones quibus intellectus illius finem determinat, obedit natura voluntati, sicut ex motu locali hominis patet: quantum vero ad illas actiones in quibus ei finem non determinat, non obedit, sicut in actu nutrimenti et augmenti. Ex iis ergo colligitur quod id quod ex necessitate natura agit, impossibile est esse principium agens, cum determinetur sibi finis ab alio. Et sic patet quod impossibile est Deum agere ex necessitate naturae". Cf. Aquinas on Creation, cit., p. 57 "...since we know that being is the perfection of all perfections, the ultimate instance of being must be the instance of ultimate perfection. Since freedom is a perfection, we know that God must be perfectly free. The fact that God's freedom is demonstrable indicates that the position of the emanationists, namely that God causes necessarily, is demonstrably false".
17 ab-solutus.
18 Cfr. CG. III, 99: "Deus autem operatur per voluntatem et non per necessitatem naturae...Igitur minores effectus, qui fiunt per causas inferiores potest facere immediate absque propriis causis".
19 Cfr. J.J. Haldane, in J.J.C. Smart and J.J. Haldane, Atheism and Theism, p. 163: "What I wish to emphasize however, against a common assumption among theists who claim to believe in the miraculous , is that it is a mistake to think of miracles as interventions from outside creation. The miraculous belongs to the category of the preternatural..., but as Aquinas very soberly explains in his chapters on miracles in the Summa contra Gentiles III, God's special actions are additions or subtractions within an order in which he is already active". Moreover it is not strange to believe thar God is interested in our lives. On the contrary it would be anthropomorfic to believe the opposite.
20 Cfr. J.J. Haldane in Atheism and Theism, p. 106: "The emergence of life and the start of speciation call for explanations and what reductionism has to offer fails to provide these, giving at best a blank cheque to chance, which is to say offering no intelligible explanation at all"; p. 119: "...the structure of the conceptual order, which is expressed in judgements and actions, is richer and more abstract than that of the natural order, and the character of this difference makes it difficult to see how the materialist could explain the former as arising out of the latter".
21 Cfr. De pot. III, 14; III, 17; ST. I, 46, 2.
22 Cfr. In II Sent. d.1, q.1, a.2 ad 2.
23 We can speak of epistemic and ethical vices, "habitus" that are the opposite of epistemic and ethical virtues.
24 Cfr. W. E. Carroll, Thomas Aquinas and Big-bang Cosmology, p. 6: "The contention of several proponents of the new theories is that the law of physics are sufficient to account for the origin and existence of the universe. If this be true, then, in a sense, we live in a universe which needs no explanation beyond itself, a universe which has sprung into existence spontaneously from a cosmic nothingness".
25 E. Agazzi, Science and Metaphysics before Nature in Man and Nature, edited by George F. McLean, Oxford University Press, Calcutta-Madras 1978, pp. 7-8. By the same author cf. Science and Metaphysics: Two Kinds of Knowledge, "Epistemologia" XI (1988), p. 18-19: "Anyone who speaks about something in particular must have understood that something in a certain way, this way reflecting in its turn the person's understanding of other more general features of reality. In this sense it is impossible not to have an unconscious metaphysics, articulated into several levels. Science is no exception to this condition, since it cannot be pursued without one's using certain criteria of intelligibility which are prior to the specific tasks it involves. In fact every advancement of some science which has been presented as a 'liberation from metaphysics' has actually been tantamount to discarding a particular metaphysical framework and accepting (often unconsciously) a different one". Cf. also E. Agazzi, The Universe as a Scientific and Philosophical Problem in E. Agazzi and A. Cordero (eds.), Philosophy and the Origin and Evolution of the Universe, Kluwer Academic Publishers, 1991, p. 42 passim: "In fact we must say that the physical concept of causality does indeed exclude the possibility of an uncaused cause (otherwise every causal explanation would be intrinsically arbitrary , since we might always suggest of any phenomenon that it is simply caused by itself), while admitting that the concept of causality at its highest level of generality (i.e. at a metaphysical level, does not exclude the possibility of an uncaused cause. Now it is certain that if this concept appears to be logically sound in itself, we cannot refuse to apply it, provided we remain conscious that the way in which it is applied defines its domain of application: this means that if we apply it in cosmology, we are ipso facto making a claim of 'metaphysical cosmology'. For instance: if we do not pay attention to the metaphysical level, "we can very well live with the idea of Universe as the uncaused cause, but this simply means (unconsciously) accepting an immanentist, rather than a transcendentist, metaphysics".
26 We have to stress particularly the experience of something that now exists and then will not exist any more ("defectibilitas rerum").
27 See ST. I, 2, 3.
28 Cfr. CG. I, 13. See S.T. Davis, God, Reason and Theistic Proofs, Edinburgh University Press, Edinburgh 1997, p. 70-73.
29 Aquinas thinks that there is a potential infinity (on the level of quantity), but that there is not an actual infinity of finite beings (cf. ST. I, 7, 4). The only actual infinite is God. Cf. CG. I, 43: "...non potest infinitas Deo attribui ratione multitudinis nullamque in eo compositionem vel partium vel accidentium inveniri...Secundum etiam quantitatem continuam infinitus dici non potest: cum ostensum sit eum incorporeum esse. Relinquitur igitur investigare an secundum spiritualem magnitudinem esse infinitum ei conveniat". Cfr. Quodlib I: "...Deus autem omnibus modis est infinitus". Cf. also De ver. XXIX, 3. Cf. ST. III, 10, 3 ad 1; De pot. I, 2.
30 See A. Campodonico, Experience of Reality, Integrity and God, Proceedings of the Summer Thomistic Institute 1997, Notre Dame University Press, Notre Dame (in press).
31 It is noteworthy that also scientific language has metaphorical-symbolic roots, although it tries to reach univocity of meaning.
32 It is noteworthy that Thomas holds that the perfections we found out in our experience, if they are infinite, they are never subsistent, instead if they are participated by a concrete being, that means compound, they are always and necessarily finite. Cf. CG. I, 30: "Nam nomine res exprimimus eo modo quo intellectus concipimus. Intellectus autem noster , ex sensibus cognoscendi initium sumens, illum modum non transcendit qui in rebus sensilibus invenitur, in quibus aliud est forma et habens formam, propter formae et materiae compositionem. Forma vero in his rebus invenitur quidem simplex, sed imperfecta, utpote non subsistens: habens autem formam invenitur quidem subsistens, sed non simplex, immo concretionem habens. Unde intellectus noster, quidquid significat ut subsistens, significat in concretione: quod vero ut simplex, significat non ut quod est, sed ut quo est. Et sic in omni nomine, a nobis dicto, quantum ad modum significandi, imperfectio invenitur, quae Deo non competit, quamvis res significata aliquo eminenti modo Deo conveniat". In particular: in our experience the act of existing is an infinite perfection which is never subsistent, on the contrary, a human person is a concrete being, actually existent, but it does not coincide with an infinite perfection.
33 Cfr. F. Nietzsche, The gay science, fr. 110, 111, 115.
34 S. Hawking proposes the model of an universe unbounded, but finite. Also the hypothesis of many or infinite universes " in short appears as entirely ad hoc, introduced only to avoid what for the naturalist is an unpalatable conclusion, viz., that the general regularities and particular fine tuning are due to the agency of a designer - et hoc dicimus Deum" (cf. J.J. Haldane, in Atheism and Theism, p. 127).
35 Aquinas on Creation, translated with an Introduction and notes by S.E. Baldner & W. Carroll, Pontifical Institute of Mediaeval Studies, Toronto, Canada 1997, p. 37-38.
36 Cfr. J.J. Smart in Atheism and Theism: "One sort of pantheist may think of the universe as a giant brain - stars, galaxies and clusters of galaxies perhaps playing the part of the micro physical particles that make up our own nervous system. I shall take it that such a form of pantheism is implausible and far- fetched. There is absolutely no evidence that the universe, however large it may be, could be a giant brain".
37 S. T. Davis, God, Reasons and Theistic Proofs, p. 186.
38 Cfr. J.J. Haldane, in Atheism and Theism, p. 152: "...the idea of thought conjoining and opposing various elements seems to belong to the sphere of psychology rather than that of reason per se. Yet it is precisely reason as such, and not an empirical psychology, that we are led to ascribe to a transcendent cause on the basis of order observed in nature". Cf. also M. Scheler, Zur Idee des Menschen, Werke, Francke, Bern-München 1954, Band III; Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die Materiale Wertethik. Neuer Versuche der Grundlegung eines ethischen Personalismus, Werke, Band II, Bern 1954, p. 411-413.
39 Cfr. ibid, p. 22: "The Naturalist cannot condemn other people's thoughts because they have irrational causes and continue to believe his own which have (if Naturalism is true) equally irrational causes" and p. 38: "If we are to continue to make moral judgements (and whatever we say we shall in fact continue) then we must believe that the conscience of man is not a product of Nature. It can be valid only if it is an offshoot of some absolute moral wisdom, a moral wisdom which exists absolutely 'on its own' and is not a product of non- moral, non-rational Nature".
40 C. S. Lewis, Miracles, p. 87.
41 The latter is the frame of what E. Husserl called the life-world (Lebenswelt), which is the background of modern science. See Die Krisis der europäischen Wissenschaften un die transzendentale Phänomenologie, Martinus Nijoff, The Hague 1959.
42 E. Agazzi, Science and Metaphysics: Two Kinds of Knowledge, p. 14-15.
43 J.J. Haldane, On coming home to (Metaphysical) Realism, "Philosophy", 71(1996), pp. 287-96.
44 See J. J. Haldane, in Atheism and Theism, p. 97: "Reductionists often confuse formal natural and material composition. In their concern to show that ultimately there is nothing more than 'atoms in the void' or 'energy plus space- time', they overlook or underestimate the significance of the hierarchy of forms within which matter is held together. I am not at all suggesting that one go in the opposite direction and say that what individual things are made of, and what, if anything, everything in the cosmos is made of, is unimportant for an understanding of the natural order; but I am claiming that the real science, as contrasted with the reductionist philosopher's ambition for it, is happy to recognise a variety of features and levels of natural being, and can proceed very well without progressive elimination of one sphere after another, collapsing the structure of science down to the atomic core that is physics". See also A. Campodonico, Experience of Reality, Integrity and God (in press). On the peculiarity of human person see D. Braine, The Human Person. Animal & Spirit, University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame (Indiana) 1992, part 2.