...quia in illo loco 1 p., q. 13 agit de analogia magis dialectice quam metaphysice, scilicet ut tenet se ex parte nominum, non ex parte rerum (de nominibus Dei ibi agebat). Sicut autem ad analogiam metaphysice attenditur inaequalitas ex parte rerum, ita in analogia dialectice considerata attenditur inaequalitas in modo significandi et nominandi.{2}How curious then that John of St Thomas can begin his discussion of analogy as an antepredicament with these words: "Difficultates de analogia, quae satis metaphysice sunt, ita copiose et subtiliter ab Caietano disputatae ip opusc. de Analogia nominum, ut nobis locum non reliquerit quid quam aliud excogitandi."{3}
What is
puzzling about John's attitude
here is that he accepts the view
that the analogy of names is
metaphysical and that its
metaphysical character is made
evident in a work whose title
indicates that it is concerned
with names. But the analogy of
names, John has said,
constitutes a dialectical or
logical problem. How then can
the analogy of names be
metaphysical? And, if it is, why
is John introducing a treatment
of it into his work on logic?
Analogy as it
covers inequality on the part of
the signification of a common
name is a logical question
according to John of St Thomas,
yet Cajetan's work on the
analogy of names presents a
metaphysical doctrine. This
confusion is not peculiar to
John. It is not unusual to find
an allusion to the logical
doctrine on analogical names in
studies devoted to analogy, but
it is extremely rare that there
is something more than an
allusion. Most authors prefer to
concern themselves with what
they feel is the metaphysical
doctrine on the analogy of
names. In the light of this, we
want to stress that, for St
Thomas, the analogy of names is
a logical doctrine; moreover
most texts brought forward in
interpretations of analogy as
metaphysical are clearly written
from a logical point of view.
Once it is seen that the analogy
of names is a logical doctrine,
the present study, whose title
might seem to indicate that it
offers a partial analysis of
analogy, can be seen as an
attempt at a formal treatment of
the problem.
The analogy
of names is a logical question.
To this assertion it might be
objected that "analogy" is used
in many ways, that it is itself
an analogous term. This is a
very valuable objection because
it indicates that, even if there
should be a metaphysical problem
of analogy, there is a prior
problem concerned with words -
in this case, with the word
"analogy" that is analogous, and
to understand what this means is
to understand something about
the way this word signifies many
things. This is a logical
matter. To say this is not to
say that "analogy" in every one
of its uses signifies a logical
relation, but it is to say that
one of its uses will tell us how
the one term "analogy" can mean
many things, one of which is a
logical relation. No one who
favors a metaphysical
interpretation of the analogy of
names has ever attempted to
apply this to "analogy" itself
even while taking obvious
delight in reminding us that
"analogy" is analogous. It does
not seem too much to say that,
unless one can explain what he
means by saying that "analogy"
is analogous, he is begging the
whole question of the analogy of
names.
St Thomas is
hardly ambiguous on the nature
of analogical signification.
Consider, for example, his
remarks on the various modes of
unity distinguished by
Aristotle.{4} "Primo distinguit
modos unius naturaliter, idest
secundum conditiones in rebus
inventas. Secundo vero logice,
idest secundum intentiones
logicales..."{5} What are the
members of the division
according to logical intentions?
"Ponit aliam divisionem unius,
quae est magis logica; dicens
quod quaedam sunt unum numero,
quaedam specie, quaedam genere,
quaedam analogia."{6} Can this
be dismissed as an isolated
remark, perhaps dictated by the
text being commented rather than
by his own views on analogy?
Hardly, when we notice that St
Thomas usually speaks of
analogical signification by
comparing it with univocation
and equivocity; it is difficult
to find a text on the analogy of
names where this comparison is
not made.{7} The obvious
significance of the comparison
is that the things compared are
in the same order. But to be
named equivocally or univocally
is surely not something which
would be numbered among the
accidents of things as they
exist in rerum natura.
To be named happens to things as
they are known by us; that is
why the modes of signification
fall to the consideration of the
logician. They are indeed the
first consideration of the Categories
and it was in commenting on that
work that Cajetan saw the need
for a separate treatise on
analogous names. At that time,
he experiences no difficulty in
recognizing the logical
character of the problem.{8} We
could safely assume, then that
the analogy of names, like
equivocity and univociaty, is a
logical intention, is in fact an
antepredicament. But we do not
have to assume that this is the
view of St. Thomas; he tells us
this quite explicitly.
Dicendum quod animal dictum de animali vero et de picto, non dicitur pure aequivoce: sed Philosophus largo modo accipit aequivoca, secundum quod includunt in se analoga. Quia et ens, quod analogice dicitur, aliquando dicitur aequivoce praedicari de diversis praedicamentis.{9}The point of comparing analogy with equivocation and univocation is that each is a second intention, each falls to the consideration of the logician. Not only is analogical signification an antepredicament, it is as well a kind of equivocation. Thus to remark that we have in the works of St Thomas no formal and per se consideration of the analogy of names is much the same thing as saying that we have no commentary by him on the Categories of Aristotle.
St Thomas
could not be clearer on the
status of the analogy of names:
it is a logical doctrine to be
discussed in terms of what is
formal to logical discussions
and, above all, to be divided by
properly logical criteria. By
attaching nearly every statement
on the analogy of names to
equivocation, St Thomas makes it
difficult for us to treat the
analogy of names as something
other than a logical intention.
And yet the very texts on which
this obvious judgment is based
have occasioned statements of
the profoundly metaphysical
character of the analogy of
names. What is the reason for
this misunderstanding?
It would be
too facile to lay the entire
blame for it on Cajetan. There
is a host of difficulties in the
texts of St Thomas. Generally
speaking, this is due to the
fact that St Thomas always
introduces the doctrine on the
analogy of names in function of
a particular problem, when he is
discussing things which happen
to be named analogously. Side by
side with quite general
statements as to what it means
for things to be named
analogously are found statements
about the determinate things
under consideration, things
which happen to found the second
intention. Because of this, the
real considerations can seem to
be part and parcel of the mode
of signification which is the
analogy of names. Thus because
the things named healthy
analogically are these particulr
things with these particular
characteristics, and those named
being analogically are things
with these determinate
characteristics, the real
differences between these groups
of things can seem to be
differences in the mode of being
named which they have in common.
The division of analogy
resulting from such confusion
can only be regarded as a gross
identification of the logical
and real orders.
When we add
to such contextual difficulties
the discrepancy, noted by both
Cajetan and Sylvester, {10}
between the use of the Greek ἀναλογία and the
Latin analogia, an
almost insuperable obstacle to
and understanding of St Thomas'
doctrine is erected - if one
forgets that St Thomas must be
numbered among the latini,
not the graeci.
How often, in commenting on the
Metaphysics
does St Thomas speak of analogy
where Aristotle has not used the
Geek term, but rather the phrase
"things said in many ways."{11}
Are we to discount St Thomas'
remarks because
κατ' ἀναλογίαν or ἀναλογία
does not occur in Aristotle? How
absurd, and yet we have seen
that this is precisely the
tendency of Cajetan and, less
clearly, Sylvester. To strive
for a one-to-one correspondence
of doctrine between what
Aristotle tends to call
ἀναλογία and analogia
is wrong-headed at best, since
the correspondence is obviously
lacking. this lack of
correspondence has nothing to
do, need it be said, with the
question of a correspondence of
doctrine between what Aristotle
tends to call
πολλαχῶς λέγεται and St
Thomas analogice dicuntur
a question , moreover, that we
are not posing. We hope only to
make some small contribution to
the effort to rescue St Thomas'
doctrine on the analogy of names
fromt the vast confusion into
which it has fallen in the
literature, the more so because
we are convinced that stripped
of the accretions of quasi
mystical obfuscation, that
doctrine will be revealed as an
important statement on what
might be called the systematic
ambiguity of certain words.
The stage
having been set, the nature of
the study which follows can be
at least partially foreseen. If
St Thomas makes analogical
signification a logical matter,
we must determine what for him
logic is. Then we must examine
his views on signification in
general, after which we can
profitably turn to an initial
statement on the analogy of
names. In going on to discuss
the division of things named
analogically, we shall look at
length at the texts which
suggested to Cajetan his hybrid,
tripartite division. Then, after
discussing knowing by analogy
and analogical causes, we shall
say something about the divine
names, a problem which, more
than any other, occasioned the
remarks of St Thomas which form
the basis of the present
interpretation.
{1} De nominum analogia,
ed. cit., nn. 1, 29.
{2} John of St Thomas, Cursus
Philosophicus, ed.
Reiser, (2nd edition, Rome;
1948), Tome I, p. 490b.
{3} Ibid., p.
481b. Emphasis ours.
{4} Metaphysics,
Delta, 6.
{5} In V Metaphys.,
lect. 7, n. 848.
{6} Ibid., lect.
8, n. 876.
{7} Cf. Ia,
q. 13, a. 5; In
IV Metaphys., lect. 1,
n. 535; De
principiis naturae,
(ed. Spiazzi), cap. 6, n. 366; In
XI Metaphys., lect. 3,
n. 2197; Q.D.
de pot., q. 7, a.7,
etc.
{8} Cajetan, Commentaria
in Praedicmenta Aristotelis,
ed. cit., pp.
8-14.
{9} Ia, q. 13, a.
10, ad 4. Cf. In
I Metaphys., lect. 14,
n. 224.
{10} De nominum analogia,
ed. cit., n. 20; In I Contra
Gentiles, cap. 34, n.
VII: "...sciendum est quod
analogiae nomen graecum est
vocabulum, et aliter accipitur a
Graecis, aliter a nonnulliis
Latinis." Cf. John of St Thomas,
op. cit., p.
512b42.
{11} Notably Aristotle, Metaphysics,
Gamma, 2, 1003a33 and St Thomas,
In IV Metaphys.,
lect. 1, n. 535.
© 2012 by the Estate of Ralph McInerny.
All rights reserved including the right to translate
or reproduce this book or parts thereof in any form.